United States
          Environmental Protection
          Agency
            Policy. Planning,
            And Evaluation
            (PM-221)
EPA 230-07-90-079
June 1990
EPA
The Relevance Of
Willingness-To-Pay
Estimates Of The Value
Of A Statistical Life In
Determining Wrongful
Death Awards
EPA
230-
07-
90-079
c.2


-------

-------
fcYA*
                                                   EPA-230-07-90-079
                THE RELEVANCE OF WILLINGNESS-TO-PAY ESTIMATES OF
                         THE VALUE OF A STATISTICAL LIFE IN
                       DETERMINING WRONGFUL DEATH AWARDS
                                   Lauraine G. Chestnut
                                    Daniel M. Violette*
                                        June 1990
                    Forthcoming, Journal of Forensic Ecpnomjcg. August 1990
             The authors are economists with RCG/Hagler, Bailly, Inc., P.O. Drawer O, Boulder,
             Colorado, 80306.  This work was support by the U.S. Environmental Protection
             Agency under contract  number 68-W8-0038.  The  authors thank Ann  Fisher,
             Maureen Cropper, Ted  Miller, Larry Braslow, Kip Viscusi, and Bob Rowe for
             comments and suggestions on earlier versions of the paper. The opinions expressed
             and conclusions presented are those of the authors.
                                                                /U460

-------

-------
INTRODUCTION

There is a fairly extensive literature in economics concerning the dollar amount individuals
are willing to pay (or dollar compensation they are willing to accept) to obtain a small
reduction (increase) in the risks of fatal injury.  From the results of these studies it is
possible to calculate an average dollar value per statistical life using the average change in
risk and the average dollar value for this change in risk.

These willingness-to-pay studies have been widely reviewed for their potential applicability
in evaluating  government  regulations  involving changes  in (small) risks across a given
population group (see, for example, Violette and Chestnut  1983  and Fisher et al. 1989).
Although the use of benefit-cost analysis to evaluate policies aimed at protecting human life
remains somewhat controversial, most  economists agree (with various qualifications) that
these types of "Value of life" estimates are the appropriate dollar values to use in this type
of benefit-cost analysis.

Recently, willingness-to-pay (WTP) estimates have found their way into legal cases involving
compensation for wrongful death, and questions are being raised about the appropriateness
of the use of  these estimates in this new area  (see Miller 1989).  This specific  issue has
not  been  widely addressed  in  the  economics literature, but  is  important because
compensation amounts in wrongful death cases  are being decided  by the courts every day,
and any insight that the economics  literature might add to this difficult process would be
helpful. What underlies the difficulty  faced by the courts is that most parties agree that
compensating survivors for only their financial loss is not adequate. Compensation on these
grounds does not  provide the right incentives for accident prevention, and it does  not seem
fair to claim that directly provable financial losses fully compensate the parties that have
suffered an intense, personal loss  with  its attending  grief  (although in  some  instances
compensation for financial losses is all that the law allows).  Even with these compelling
reasons, putting a dollar value on the non-financial loss is very difficult. The willingness-
to-pay estimates seem appealing because  we know they reflect more than just the  potential
financial loss involved in the risk of death. Whether they are an  appropriate measure of
fair compensation in the case of a wrongful death is another question.

This paper presents the key issues that underlie this question and discusses the theoretical
and  empirical information available in  the  economics literature.   The  answer to this
question is not a simple yes or no.  It is a conditional maybe in some circumstances, with
remaining uncertainties that cannot be resolved without further empirical research. What
is critical is identifying the  purpose  or intent of the wrongful death award and contrasting
this with what is reflected in the WTP  estimates  that have been obtained in  economic
studies.  There are some potentially important differences between the WTP estimates and
the legal definitions of compensation that apply  in wrongful death cases, but the courts are
having to make dollar decisions on these awards everyday and our  intent  in this paper is
to explore whether the WTP estimates might provide any  positive information that would
be helpful in this process.

-------
WRONGFUL DEATH COMPENSATION

A wrongful death case typically involves an accidental or premature death of an individual
that can be attributed to a specific cause.  Depending on the specific laws that apply,
obtaining compensation  from an identified responsible party may or may not require
demonstration of negligence on the part of the responsible party. Often a two-step process
is involved.  First, a determination regarding negligence  is made, including potential
contributory negligence on the part of the deceased. The result of this determination is
an assignment of a percentage of responsibility for the death to the defendant.  Second, a
total dollar amount of compensation is determined to which the percentage assigned to the
defendant is applied The focus of this paper is on the second step of this process, the
determination of the total dollar payment that would be an appropriate compensation for
the loss associated with the death of the individual.  This can be treated as independent of
any determination of negligence.

The purpose of wrongful death compensation is not unambiguous. There are legal statutes
that define what the compensation should reflect, when a wrongful  death has been
determined, and these vary from state to state.  There are also social welfare theories that
suggest levels of compensation that would further various social goals, such as the optimal
provision of accident prevention efforts.  These often  are  very different from the legal
requirements.  This paper considers the following five definitions of compensation which
are often used in the law or in the economics literature:1

                      Alternative Definition;; of Compensation
                                                                      j
       1.     replacement of financial support lost to survivors due to premature death

       2.     a dollar measure of all support lost to survivors  including financial support,
             household and childcare services, companionship, parental guidance, moral
             support, love, etc.

       3.     a dollar measure of the full loss in utility  (well-being) to survivors including
             item (2) and any additional pain and  suffering (grief) due to the loss of a
             loved one

       4.     compensation to the decedent's estate  for the loss of income and enjoyment
             of  life; essentially a dollar measure of the loss in utility (well-being) to the
             deceased

       5.     a dollar measure of the value of a (statistical or unidentified) human life to
             the individual at risk, which includes financial and non-financial factors as well
             as  concerns of the individual regarding  the potential effect of his or her death
             on survivors
    1 Awards in wrongful death cases sometimes also include punitive damages, but this
involves a different purpose than compensation and is not the focus of this paper.

-------
The first three categories are various definitions of what it might mean to "compensate"
survivors. Item (3) defines a dollar measure of the total loss to survivors in the event of
a premature death. Items (1) and (2) are subsets of item (3), each excluding some part of
the loss.  Item (1) is a fairly straightforward concept although uncertainty exists because it
is necessary to estimate the future earnings that are lost because of the premature death.
There is general agreement that immediate family members of the  deceased (typically
spouses, children, and sometimes parents) should be compensated at least this amount, but
some disagreement exists as to whether the amount that would  have been spent  on
consumption  by the deceased should be excluded; and  on whether and how to quantify
lost household and childcare  services.   Still, current techniques  used to estimate this
component of compensation are probably adequate. However, it is clear that the financial
aspect alone, however it is measured, probably understates the total loss to survivors due
to an individual's premature death.

Statutes in some states define compensation as in item (2). For example, California statutes
define compensation to victims (dependents) in the case of wrongful death of an individual
to include loss of financial support, loss of "love, companionship, comfort, affection, society,
solace or moral support," and where applicable, loss of enjoyment of sexual relations and
physical assistance in the operation and  maintenance of the home.2  Consideration of pain
and suffering related to grief is specifically excluded.  The California statutes also give
specific definitions of who is  to be compensated: generally this includes  only spouses,
natural and adopted children, and parents of minor children.

Item  (3) is more of a welfare economics definition of compensation, although it is similar
to that defined by law when pain and suffering of survivors as well as their loss of financial
and non-financial support are to be considered. In welfare economics, the formal definition
of compensation is the change in income that would restore the survivors to their previous
(pre-accident) levels of utility (or well-being).  This would include compensation for all
financial and non-financial losses to all  the survivors affected by the death.

Item  (4) defines a measure of the loss to the deceased individual. Miller (1989) notes that
wrongful death compensation statutes  in several  states allow for  compensation  to the
decedent's estate for lost enjoyment of life, along with compensation for lost productivity.
In this case the loss is measured in  terms  of the loss  to the  deceased, with the estate
standing as the representative, rather than in terms of the loss to the  survivors.

The fifth category defines the value of a statistical life used in the economics literature.
Interpreting this as an appropriate measure of compensation in the case of a wrongful death
is related to a concept of economic efficiency, which is widely discussed in the economics
literature (see for example, Viscusi 1983), but is not necessarily the primary concern in the
legal  arena. Some analysts hypothesize that improving economic efficiency is an underlying
    2 This is taken from California Jury Instructions. Civil, prepared by the Committee on
Standard Jury Instructions, Civil, Superior Court of Los Angeles County, California, West
Publishing Co., St. Paul, MN, 1986.

-------
social goal behind the laws allowing for compensation to survivors in wrongful death cases
(see for example, Brown 1973), but this is not explicitly stated in the laws themselves. This
definition of compensation  focuses on  the deterrent  effect that  requiring payment  of
compensation will have on those who have an influence on  the amount of risk to which
others are exposed.

The first four definitions of compensation are all ex post in nature in that they involve some
measure of a loss that has already occurred.  Although the fifth  definition is  also for a
payment after an accident, the magnitude is determined by the  conditions that existed
before the accident (ex ante conditions).  This is  because the intent of the fifth definition
is to provide incentives for an optimal allocation of resources to accident prevention.  The
implications of the differences between the ex ante and ex post perspectives are discussed
in a later section of the paper.

WILLINGNESS-TO-PAY ESTIMATES FOR CHANGES IN  FATAL RISKS

The willingness-to-pay studies attempt to estimate the change in income for an individual
that is equivalent in terms of a change in utility (well-being) to a change in the individual's
risk of fatal injury.  To make this more concrete, we will focus on analyses of the wage-
risk trade-off. Wage-risk trade-offs are the most common contexts in which such values are
believed to be revealed.  Wage-risk studies attempt to  estimate the additional  amount of
wages that must be paid for individuals to accept jobs with greater risks of fatal injury.  This
compensation is  ex ante  because  it  is  paid before a potential  accident has occurred.
Abstracting from the  limitations of the empirical  estimation procedures (which are not
trivial, but are not the focus of this discussion), economic welfare theory indicates that the
estimates obtained with this analysis can be expected to reflect the expected value (loss) to
the individual of an increased risk of his or her own death.  This can be expected to include
the following components:

       1.     potential loss in one's own utility in the event of one's own death, including
             the loss in expected utility of future consumption, loss of utility derived from
             living independent of consumption, and  any disutility (pain and suffering)
             associated with the death itself

       2.     potential loss  in  one's  own utility due  to  the potential financial loss to
             survivors in the event of one's death

       3.     potential loss in one's own  utility due to the utility loss for survivors due to
             loss of one's companionship, love, moral  support, parental guidance, etc.

The potential loss in one's own utility in the event of  death is at least equivalent to the
present value of future consumption that would be lost.  For an individual with no financial
dependents, it could be expected that component (1) would be greater than or,  at the very
minimum, equal to the present value of expected future income of the individual. For an
individual with financial dependents, some of. the expected future income would  have
benefited the dependents, thereby spreading the present value of one's future income across
components (1) and (2).

-------
A potential increase in willingness to pay when there are dependents  may occur due to
component (3).  Cropper and Sussman (1988) refer to this as a potential "family existence
effect" and provide very preliminary empirical evidence that such an effect exists.  They
define the family existence effect as utility the individual derives from the existence of other
family members that is independent of their consumption.  The individual may also be
concerned about the potential effect of his or her death on other relatives and friends who
may not be financially  dependent, but who share some companionship  and love.

Looking from the employer's point of view, the 'Value of life" is the  risk premium that he
must pay (spread across all employees) in order to operate in circumstances when there is
an average risk  of one death per year per X number of employees. This risk premium
raises the wages he must pay, compared with an otherwise equivalent job with a lower risk
of fatality.  The employer will have incentives to reduce risks to employees to the point
where the costs per life saved of accident prevention efforts just equal the value per life lost
he must pay (hi  higher wages).

Fisher et al. (1989) summarize  the range of results  found in the most  credible wage-risk
studies  to date and conclude that the most credible results  fall between $1.6 and $8.5
million  per statistical life saved.  Miller (1990) has conducted a similar  review and drawn
somewhat different conclusions, suggesting a most credible range of $1 to $3.1 million per
statistical life saved. Risks of death on the job are typically around one per year per 10,000
workers.  A value per statistical  life of $3 million means  that each worker is being
compensated an average of $300 per year for accepting a risk of death  of .0001 per year.
It is important to note  that these ranges of $160 to $850 and of $100 to  $310 are ranges in
the average compensation required for this level of risk for the samples of workers used in
the studies. These studies do not tell us how any one individual, either in these samples
or in other groups in society, might need to be compensated to accept this level of risk; nor
do they tell us how much  compensation would be  required,  on average, for workers to
accept substantially higher  levels of risk.

When a worker accepts this "risk premium," the implied value per statistical life might be
interpreted as an implicit value the individual is putting on his or her life in this context,
but this interpretation is subject  to  some specific  assumptions.   The most  important
assumption behind this interpretation is that the risk premium is related to the expected
value of the potential loss.  Using the example of a  $300 risk premium  for a .0001 risk of
death, $300 is the expected value of a .0001 risk of a potential loss of $3,000,000.  It is not
clear that the average person responds  to risks in this way, and  in fact there is some
evidence that the expected value of a potential loss is not a very good predictor of the value
an individual places on the potential for even a simple financial loss  (see Violette and
Chestnut 1983, Chapter 5).  In addition,  even if the expected value is  an acceptable
interpretation of the risk premium, we do not know whether the implicit  value of life is the
same when different kinds  of risks or different levels of risks are involved.

-------
COMPARISON   BETWEEN   WRONGFUL    DEATH   COMPENSATION   AND
WILLINGNESS-TO-PAY ESTIMATES

In this section of the paper we discuss differences between wrongful death compensation
and the willingness-to-pay (WTP) estimates that are relevant for most or all of the potential
compensation definitions.

Survivors Versus Deceased

The most striking difference between the first three potential definitions of wrongful death
compensation and the WTP estimates is that the former concern the effect of a death on
the survivors, while the latter concern the change in utility for the individuals facing a risk
of death. While concern for survivors (especially dependents) is expected to be a factor in
determining the compensation an individual would require to accept a given risk of fatal
injury, concern  for self is expected to be an important, if not the most important, factor.
Further, it is not  just  a  matter of subtracting the component of  the  WTP estimate
attributable to concern for self (which is not likely to be a simple  empirical task in any
case), because the effect of a change in a dependent's utility is not necessarily associated
with a one-to-one change in the individual's utility. If we assume, however, that the family
is a utility maximizing unit and that the individual's decisions regarding employment reflect
the family's utility function, then the WTP estimate can be expected to exceed the utility
loss to the dependents, because it includes the value the individual places on his or her own
potential loss as well as on the potential loss to  dependents.3

y*y Post Versus EK Ante Compensation

The estimates obtained in the WTP studies are ex ante values, meaning that they are based
on conditions in existence  before the potential accident. Wrongful death compensation is
ex post because it occurs after the accident has happened.  This difference might affect the
level of compensation that would be required, depending on how compensation is defined.
    3 This is a point on which we disagree with Johnson's (1989) interpretation of the WTP
estimates. He references Fisher et al. (1989) as the source of his information on the WTP
estimates and proposes a certain interpretation of these estimates for use in determining
wrongful death compensation.  Johnson argues that because the accident victim is not
known when the individual makes the employment or other risk accepting decision and
because the risk to the individual is very small, the WTP estimates reflect the  value of
protecting some other (unidentified) person's life  rather than the individual's own. This
contradicts the standard interpretation of the WTP estimates in  the economics literature,
which is that they reflect the individual's concern for his or her  own safety in the face of
some probability of a fatal accident. The fact that the probability of an accident is small
does not change this. The basic premise of welfare economics  is that individuals act to
maximize their own utility.

-------
Viscusi  (1983)  defines  two measures  of compensation, and argues  that the difference
between these two measures is related to differences in the ex ante and ex post marginal
utility of income. One definition of compensation is the amount that restores everyone to
their  original  (pre-accident)  level  of utility.   Viscusi  suggests  that  the amount  of
compensation that would restore the original utility is related to the WTP estimates from
wage-risk  studies.  However, he does not fully address potential differences between the
WTP estimates and a measure of compensation that would restore original utility, when the
accident involves something more than a financial loss (as a wrongful death certainly does).

If only a financial loss is involved, the level of compensation that would restore the original
level of utility is an amount equivalent to the financial loss.  In this circumstance, there is
no significant difference expected  between ex ante and ex post compensation.  The risk
neutral  individual will be  indifferent between being compensated before the  potential
accident by the expected value of the loss (the magnitude of the potential loss multiplied
by the probability of the loss occurring) or being compensated after  the accident by the
amount of the loss.  However, the WTP  estimates and the wrongful death compensations
concern a situation where the loss involves substantially more than money. In this situation,
it is not an appropriate interpretation of the WTP estimate to say that a payment of the
implied value of a statistical life in the event of an accidental death will restore the pre-
accident level of utility. After death, it is impossible to compensate the individual for the
loss of his or her own life and it is unlikely that there  is any amount of money that would
restore the spouse, children, or parents to their pre-accident level of utility. Thus, we would
argue that while there may be a finite ex ante compensation that  would restore the pre-
risk utility levels, and that this is an appropriate interpretation of the  wage-risk premium,
there is not likely to be any finite  ex post compensation that would restore, the pre-death
utility levels even for survivors.

The second definition of compensation Viscusi gives is the amount of insurance individuals
would have purchased ex ante if they could have insured themselves against the loss on an
actuarially fair basis.  He treats this as roughly equivalent to the present value of potential
lost income. Viscusi says, "If there  are no adverse health effects and all losses are financial,
this measure  is tantamount to compensation for the monetary accident costs."  He argues
that  if there  are adverse health effects (especially permanent  disability or death), this
measure will be less than  the amount that would restore the pre-accident welfare  level.
Because the individual can be expected to derive more utility from a dollar available for
consumption  before the accident rather  than after (especially if it is a fatal or seriously
debilitating accident), the individual will not insure himself for the full welfare impact of
the accident even when given the opportunity to purchase such insurance on an actuarially
fair basis.  Ex ante life insurance  purchases, even in  an actuarially fair market, are also
likely to understate the potential losses to survivors in that the individual is not likely to be
willing  to pay  to ensure financial compensation for losses for which money is a poor
substitute (such as love, companionship, and parental guidance).  This is one possible
reason why the WTP estimates imply values per statistical lives that exceed the amount of
life insurance the average person carries.

The economic definition of ex post  compensation that would restore the original utility level
does not appear to be a practical concept to help determine wrongful death compensations,

-------
because in most cases there would be no finite amount of financial compensation that
would do this.  Much of the loss involved in a death (especially for the deceased and also
to a large extent for the survivors) is something for which money is a poor substitute.  The
question then becomes whether ex ante  measures of this potential  loss, based on what
people are doing to avoid it, are an acceptable or useful way to quantify the loss when it
comes to determining compensation after an accident has occurred.  The answer  to this
question is not necessarily going to be found with economic theorizing, but what we as
economists can contribute to this  discussion is a clear explanation  of what we think is
reflected in available ex ante measures of the value of reducing or avoiding risks of death,
and of the assumptions and uncertainties that underlie the potential use of these estimates
in wrongful death compensation determinations.

Identified Versus Statistical Individual

Another difference between wrongful death compensation and WTP estimates is often
discussed in conjunction with the ex ante and ex post comparison.  This is that wrongful
death compensation occurs when the accident victim is known and WTP estimates are
based on the situation when the accident victim is unknown. This is not really a difference
between before and after the accident, but is a difference in the level of risk faced by the
individual.  When the individual who will be injured or killed is identified, the risk he or
she faces is 100 percent.  When the individual is not identified, the risk is often small,
something much less than 100 percent.

In the case  where the victim is known, the ex ante compensation measure for the individual
at risk would be the answer to the question (however it is empirically measured): What is
the minimum increase in  income you would be willing to accept in order to voluntarily
subject yourself to this injury (with certainty that it will occur)?  With  an answer  to this
question we could say with some  confidence that the individual is indifferent between
receiving this payment before or after the injury occurs and that this amount would restore
the original level of utility if paid in compensation after the accident.  When dealing with
an injury that involves only a financial loss, this is all quite reasonable, but it becomes a bit
ridiculous when dealing with a fatal  injury, or even a seriously debilitating one.  The
question then becomes: What is the minimum increase in inheritance for your survivors that
you would accept in order to voluntarily be killed?  We guess that most people would say
(and would behave in a way that would reveal) that there is no such amount.

What this means is that there is no way to fully compensate the deceased in the case of a
wrongful death. The California  statutes seem to recognize this in focusing on the surviving
dependents of the deceased and excluding consideration of any pain  and  suffering the
deceased may have experienced. However, even if we focus on the loss in utility of the
survivors we have a similar difficulty in the case of an identified injury victim. The ex ante
question then becomes: What is the minimum increase in income you would be willing to
accept in order to voluntarily allow your loved one to be killed?  Again, we  would expect
that most people would feel that there is  no such amount. The parallel ex post question
would be: What is the minimum increase in income that would make you feel as well-off
as you felt before your loved one died? This question relieves the survivor of responsibility
for the death, but still would probably not have a finite answer for most people.

                                         8

-------
In reality, life is a risky business and everyone faces death one way or another.  In day to
day living, therefore, it is routine that people make trade-offs between income (and utility
in general) and risks of death. This is quite natural and unavoidable.  What we have in the
wage-risk studies is an estimate of the average amount an individual must be compensated
in wages in order to voluntarily accept an increased risk of fatal injury. That we can take
the change in income and multiply it by the change in risk of death  and come  up with a
dollar  per statistical life  number does not mean that this is  the  amount that would
compensate the individual or anyone else for that individual's death. Violette and Chestnut
(1983) have suggested that it would be reasonable that this dollar per statistical life number
would  vary with the level of risk involved, but this  has  not  been  firmly established
empirically. The presumption is that the necessary compensation will increase more rapidly
than the acceptable  risk and will approach infinity as the risk approaches 100 percent.  This
means that there is  probably not a single "value of life," although the amount of variation
has not been empirically determined.

Another important difference that occurs when going from the statistical individual to the
identified individual is that we go from an average across a large group to an individual.
The WTP estimates are averages for the groups sampled in each of the studies in which the
estimates have been obtained. In the wage-risk studies this  is typically working age adult
males. The WTP estimates therefore reflect average income levels, average risk aversion
attitudes, and averages of other relevant characteristics for individuals in the samples.  Any
single individual might be quite different from the average.

WILUNGNESS-TO-PAY ESTIMATES COMPARED TO ALTERNATIVE PEFINITIONS
OF COMPENSATION

In this section we compare the WTP estimates to each of the specific alternative definitions
of wrongful death compensation discussed above.  These comparisons abstract from the
general differences  discussed in the previous section.  Most of these general differences
apply as well for each of the individual comparisons.

Compensation Definition 1: Lost Future Earnings

Empirical estimates suggest that willingness to pay for small changes in risks of death imply
values per statistical life that are an order of magnitude larger than typical lifetime earnings
(on the order of a few million rather than a few hundred thousand  dollars). Whether this
is due to some sort of risk aversion, differences in the marginal utility of  income under
different states, large family existence factors, large disutility of potential pain and suffering
associated with death, or some other factor has not been fully articulated in the economics
literature.

Just because the average value per statistical life exceeds the average lifetime earnings does
not mean, however, that expected future income is fully reflected  in the WTP  estimates.
To the extent that an individual has insurance that would compensate dependents for their
loss in income in the event  of the individual's death, this potential loss  would not be
expected to be reflected  in decisions such as whether to accept a given wage for  a job with

-------
a given risk of a fatal accident.4  If the individual is fully insured, then component (2) will
be  zero and  only that portion of future  income that would  have been  used for the
individual's own consumption would be reflected in the WTP estimates.5

We conclude that the WTP estimates do not add much useful information if the desired
measure of compensation is the lost future income. Current techniques for estimating lost
future income can take account of the specific characteristics of the individual, which the
WTP estimates do not, and can be sure of excluding considerations other than lost future
income that are also reflected in the WTP  estimates.

Compensation Definition 2: Loss of All Financial and Non-Financial Support

As discussed above, it is expected that the WTP estimates will reflect the value the average
individual places on the potential loss of financial and non-financial support to survivors in
the event of his or her death.  However, it is uncertain whether the full potential loss to
survivors will be reflected in the WTP estimates.  This will depend on:

       1.     the extent to which the potential financial loss to  dependents is covered by
             life insurance

       2.     whether the individual places as much value on the potential loss of non-
             financial support as do the survivors

An analysis of typical life  insurance coverage held by individuals sampled  in wage-risk
studies might yield some insight about how much of the potential financial loss to survivors
    4 Data are probably available to empirically address this question, although we have not
done so. To determine whether the average value per statistical life includes financial loss
to dependents it would be necessary to find  out the average amount of life insurance
coverage held by individuals in the wage-risk study samples. We guess that some, but not
all, of the potential financial loss to dependents is covered by insurance on average, so that
the remaining potential  loss is reflected in the WTP estimates.

    5 This is another point on which we disagree with Johnson's (1989) interpretation of the
WTP estimates for use in wrongful death cases.  He argues that the WTP estimates do not
include any of  the lost future  income due to premature death and  reflect only the
"intangible1' loss. He makes  this claim arguing that  income is not  relevant because the
person who will die is not identified.  This makes no sense.  The average WTP will reflect
the average expected income loss, at least to the extent that  the individual would have
used this income for consumption. This component of WTP for the individual will be some
portion of the potential  loss (the probability of the loss faced by the individual multiplied
by the magnitude of the potential loss to the individual).  To say that potential lost income
to dependents is not reflected in the WTP estimates requires the strict assumption that the
average individual is fully insured for lost income to dependents in the event of his or her
death.
                                         10

-------
might be expected to be  covered elsewhere and  therefore not reflected in  the  WTP
estimates.  Whether there are significant differences between  the value  the  individual
places on the potential loss of non-financial support to survivors relative to the value the
survivors would place on this potential loss is a more difficult question. This question could
be explored in an interview approach for adults.  Where minor children are involved, we
have little recourse but to accept the assumption that the parent's decisions reflect the
utility of the child.

Other factors in  addition to  the  potential loss in financial and non-financial support to
survivors are also expected to be reflected in the WTP estimates.  If the loss of financial
and non-financial support  to the survivors is fully  reflected  in  the WTP estimates, this
means that the WTP estimates will overstate this loss to survivors by  the amounts that
reflect:

       1.     the value to the individual of the perceived enjoyment of the remainder of his
             or her expected life, including utility related to consumption  and  unrelated
             to consumption

      2.     the value to the individual  of avoiding the potential pain and suffering that
             he or she would expect to experience in the event of an accidental death

      3.     the value to the individual of preventing the pain and suffering (grief) that the
             survivors would experience in the event  of his or her death

It is probably a reasonable guess that the value to individuals of their enjoyment of their
own lives, combined with the value of avoiding  their own potential pain  and  suffering,
accounts for a large portion of the WTP estimates.  This could be explored  empirically by
examining differences in WTP for individuals with and without dependents.   Such an
examination would have to take  into account differences in the way financial  and non-
financial potential losses to survivors might enter  the WTP estimates. Separating  the
individuals' value for preventing the grief survivors  might  experience  from other non-
financial losses such as companionship and parental guidance would be  very difficult.

We conclude that the WTP estimates are likely to overstate this definition of compensation
to survivors, but that this needs  to  be verified  empirically.  There are  some  fairly
straightforward research  efforts that could reduce the  uncertainty in this conclusion.

Compensation Definition 3: Total Welfare Impact to Survivors

The  expected  relationship between  the WTP  estimates and the third  definition  of
compensation is similar to that discussed above for  the second definition. The difference
is that the pain and suffering (grief) experienced  by the survivors is included in the third
definition, bringing it closer to the WTP  estimate.

We would expect that the WTP estimate will exceed the non-financial components  of
definition 2 and definition 3 compensations if we accept the following assumptions:
                                         11

-------
       1.     due  tp  life insurance  coverage, the  WTP estimate reflects none  of the
             potential financial loss to the survivors

       2.     expected value of the potential loss is an acceptable interpretation of the risk
             premium, and if not the difference is such that the WTP estimate exceeds the
             value of the potential loss

       3.     the individual does not place significantly less value on the potential loss to
             survivors than they would place on it for themselves

       4.     the individual has an  average sized  family and  average preferences  and
             aversions with regard to life and death

       5.     the relevant  risk situation  would have evoked the same or less reaction
             (required the same or less risk premium) as the situation in which the WTP
             estimate was observed

Our conclusions about the  relationship between the WTP estimates and this definition of
compensation are  the same  as  those  given  above  for  the previous  definition of
compensation. The only difference is that the likely overstatement is reduced because the
grief related pain and suffering for survivors is included.  Especially for this definition of
compensation, which  does  not exclude any components of the loss to survivors, research
concerning how the WTP estimates are affected by concern for survivors might suggest how
to subtract the desired value  from the WTP estimate.

Compensation Definition 4; Loss to the Deceased

Wrongful death compensation laws that allow for compensation to an individual's estate for
the loss suffered by the deceased define compensation in a way that more closely matches
the WTP estimates than for laws that focus on the loss to the survivors.

It is important to note that the WTP estimates can be expected to reflect the value placed
by the individual on the financial and non-financial loss  that survivors, especially family
dependents, would experience in the event of his or her death.  Without further research
there is currently inadequate  information to say what share  of the average  WTP estimate
is attributable to this component of the value. It could be argued that this component
should be subtracted  if only  the value to the individual of his  or her life is the desired
measure.  Interdependence of utility among family members, however, makes it less than
fully clear whose value this is. A reasonable case could be made that this is a loss to the
deceased due to the responsibility and love he or she feels toward others.

An important distinction that needs to be made if the WTP estimates are  used to bound
this definition of compensation is the potential difference between the average  and the
identified  individual.   The WTP estimates give us values for the  average individual,
including average potential financial losses in the event of death. If the deceased is not
average in terms of income, then the best way to adjust for this difference is to subtract the
present value of the expected lifetime earnings for the  average individual in the samples

                                         12

-------
from which the WTP estimates were obtained, possibly adjusting for the average amount
of life insurance held by these individuals.  The remaining dollar amount can be expected
to reflect the average value of the non-financial components of the WTP estimates. If a
total dollar measure of the loss for this particular individual's  death is desired, then the
present value of their expected lifetime  earnings can be added to this  non-financial
component of the WTP estimate.  (See Miller 1989 for an example of how this might be
done.)

Compensation Definition 5: Safety Efficiency Incentives

An alternative way of viewing the social benefit of a system allowing for compensation to
survivors in wrongful death cases is to consider the incentives  it provides with regard to
accident prevention.  If we consider that society as a whole has a finite amount of resources
to spend on both ex post compensation  to  accident victims  and to ex ante accident
prevention efforts, the best allocation of the resources will be  that which minimizes the
total cost of accidents and accident prevention to society. To reach this optimization point
would mean that the total cost to society of preventing a fatality should just equal the total
benefit to society when a fatality is prevented.  If the responsible party must pay an amount
that equals the total benefit to society when a death is prevented, then that party will have
incentives to spend up to that amount on efforts to reduce  the risks of fatal accidents.  In
this case, an ex ante measure of the benefit of preventing a fatality is appropriate.

The benefit to society when a fatality is prevented includes the benefit to the individual who
is saved as well as  to family members and others.   The WTP estimates  of value per
statistical life  may be a reasonable measure of the benefit to  society of a preventing  a
fatality. This  is similar to the application  of the WTP estimates in the regulatory  arena
where they are used as a dollar measure of the average total benefit associated with the
prevention of death for an unidentified individual. To the extent that potential lost income
and medical expenditures are not reflected in the WTP estimates  due to insurance coverage,
the WTP estimate may actually  understate the total benefit of preventing a fatality.  The
WTP estimates may also understate the total benefit of preventing a fatality to the extent
that the benefits to loved ones and others  are  not fully reflected in the decisions made by
the individual.

As economists ever interested in efficiency, we see this as a legitimate use of the  WTP
estimates, but this is different from the specific legal requirements related to wrongful  death
compensation that concern only the survivors.  Changing to a consideration of the total loss
to society, including the loss to the deceased individual, would  require a conscious  social
decision to change the legal statutes related to wrongful death compensation.  We  think
that it is this perspective that probably underlies the advocacy by some economists for the
use of the WTP estimates in wrongful death compensation.  Miller (1988), for example,
does not specifically discuss this efficiency consideration, but does argue that standardization
of the wrongful death compensation procedure by using the WTP estimates would provide
potential benefits in terms  of reduced litigation costs and a reduction in the wide and
apparently capricious variation in awards.
                                         13

-------
CONCLUSIONS

A fundamental difference between the WTP estimates of the value of a statistical life and
wrongful death compensations is that the former are ex ante measures while the latter are
ex post payments.  We have considered  the economic definition of ex post compensation,
which is the amount that would restore the pre-accident level of utility (well-being), and
have concluded that this is not a very helpful concept with regard to determining wrongful
death compensations because in most cases there would be no finite amount of money that
would do this.  We are therefore willing to consider the possibility that ex ante measures,
which reflect the value individuals implicitly place on their lives when they make voluntary
tradeoffs between  income (or expenditures) and increased (or decreased) risks of death,
may provide some positive information to help in  the difficult process of determining
wrongful death compensation.

We conclude  that the  WTP estimates are potentially useful when  the definition of
compensation involves putting a dollar figure on non-financial losses  to the deceased or to
survivors.   In  both cases there are some significant uncertainties about  how the WTP
estimates should be interpreted that could be resolved with additional empirical research.
There are more  uncertainties that  need  to be  addressed  when  the  definition  of
compensation  focuses on the loss to survivors.  When the definition of compensation
involves quantifying the loss to the deceased the most important uncertainties we have
identified are:

       1.     the stability of the implicit  value of a statistical life in different circumstances

       2.     the amount of potential lost future income that is reflected in the average
             WTP estimates

       3.     the amount of variation  in the WTP estimates associated with differences in
             age and other characteristics of the individual

The first uncertainty  is significant because  the range  of circumstances for which WTP
estimates are available is limited primarily to on-the-job risks and to automobile accidents.
It is not known how much the implicit  value of a statistical life might  vary in circumstances
involving different levels and types of risks of fatalities. If the  value varies significantly,
then we are faced with a difficult question regarding what values are relevant to a particular
wrongful death case. More could be learned with further empirical research about how the
WTP estimates may vary, but it would entail a considerable  research effort.

The second uncertainty could be more easily addressed, at least approximately. Information
on typical life insurance coverage and income levels for the samples on which the available
WTP estimates are based could be used to approximate the average amount of income
expected to be reflected in the estimates. Additional work  confirming the hypothesized
effect  of insurance coverage on the inclusion of potential financial losses in the WTP
estimates would be useful.
                                         14

-------
The third uncertainty concerns the variation from the average that might be expected across
individuals. With more information about how WTP estimates vary with characteristics such
as age, it will be easier to tailor the estimates to a specific individual.

If we focus on the definitions of compensation that concern survivors of a wrongful death,
we conclude that the WTP estimates of the value of a statistical life can be expected to
systematically overstate the average non-financial loss to survivors.  Whether or not the
WTP estimates are likely to exceed the financial and non-financial loss to survivors depends
on whether the non-financial losses are overstated by more than the financial losses are
understated due to the existence of insurance.  This question is something that could be
answered  by further empirical work along the lines discussed above, but extending the
exploration to include how the WTP estimates vary with  the number of dependents the
individual has (including individuals with no dependents).  This would give us a better idea
of the size of the non-financial loss to survivors reflected in the WTP estimate.

We  suspect that it may  be a reasonable social  choice  to use WTP  type estimates in
determining wrongful death compensations in order to minimize the total social cost of
accidents and accident prevention. However, this would require a conscious social decision
to change wrongful  death compensation  laws, which would need to  be  preceded by
appropriate public discussion and debate.

REFERENCES

J.P. Brown. 1973.  'Toward an Economic Theory of Liability."  Journal of Legal Studies
2: 323-347.

ML. Cropper and F.G. Sussman. 1988.  "Families and the Economics of Risks to Life."
American Economic Review 78 (March): 255-260.

Environmental Law Institute.   1985.  "The Use of Jury Awards to Value Health Risks: A
Preliminary Assessment."  Draft report prepared for the U.S. Environmental Protection
Agency, Washington, D.C.

A. Fisher, L.G.  Chestnut, and D.V. Violette.  1989. "The Value  of Reducing Risks of
Death: A  Note on New Evidence."  Journal of Policy Analysis and Management 8: 88-100.

C.P. Gillette and T.D. Hopkins.   1988.  "Federal Agency Valuations of Human  Life."
Report to the  Administrative Conference  of the United States.

R.W. Johnson. 1989. "Loss of Human  Value of Life Economic Impact Report." Report
prepared by Robert W. Johnson and Associates, Palo Alto, California, for Speiser, Krause,
Madole, and Cook re: Crosno v. Aeromexico, August 2.

M. Lavelle.  1988.  "Placing a Price on Human Life."  The National LawLJournal. October
10.
                                        15

-------
T.R. Miller. 1988. "Willingness to Pay: Pandora's Box or Pallative for Liability Problems."
Journal of Policy Analysis and Management 7: 363-367.

T.R. Miller.   1989.  "Willingness to Pay  Comes of  Age: Will the System Survive?"
Northwestern University Law Review 83: 876*907.

T.R. Miller. 1990.  The Plausible Range for the Value of Life: Red  Herrings Among the
Mackerel this issue.

A. Ulph.  1982.  "The Role of Ex Ante and Ex Post Decisions in the Valuation of Life."
Journal of Public Economics 18:  265-276.

D.M. Violette  and L.G. Chestnut.  1983.  Valuing  Reductions in Risks: A Review of the
Empirical Estimates.  EPA-230-05-83-002.  Office of Policy Analysis, U.S. Environmental
Protection Agency, Washington, D.C.

D.M. Violette and LG. Chestnut  1989.  Valuing  Risks: New  Information on the
Willingness to Pay  for Changes  in Fatal Risks.   EPA-230-06-86-016.  Office of Policy
Planning and Evaluation, U.S. Environmental Protection Agency, Washington, D.C.

W.K. Viscusi.  1983. "Alternative Approaches to Valuing the Health Impacts of Accidents:
Liability Law  and  Prospective  Evaluations."   Law and  Contemporary  Problems 46
(Autumn): 49-68.
                                        16

-------
            DATE DUE
MAR 2
          HIGHSMITH #45115
                                                            J

-------

-------