Economic Valuation of Aquatic Ecosystems
       Anthony Fisher, Michael Hanemann,
      John Harte, Alexander Home,
   Gregory Ellis, and David Von Hippel
   University of California, Berkeley
   Final Report to U.S. Environmental
            Protection Agency

    Cooperative Agreement No. 811847
                                           October 1986

-------
                               Table of Contents
Chapter 1.    Introduction and Overview
Chapter 2.    A Suite of Indicator Variables (SIV) Index for an Aquatic
              Ecosystem
Chapter 3.    The Hysteresis Effect in the Recovery of Damaged Aquatic
              Ecosystems;  An Ecological Phenomenon with Policy Implications
Chapter 4:    Ecotoxicology and Benefit-Cost Analysis;  The Role of Error
              Propagation
Chapter 5:    Hysteresis, Uncertainty, and Economic Valuation
Chapter 6:    The Economic Concept of Benefit
Chapter 7 :     Methods of Benefit Measurement
Chapter 8:    Further Work

-------
                   CHAPTER  li INTRODUCTION AND OVERVIEW






   In this chapter we indicate the ways  in  which aquatic ecosystems are




valuable  to mankind, and make a first pass at suggesting how these values




might be  assessed.   Our object is  to give an adequate appreciation of the




many and  varied kinds of goods and services provided by aquatic  ecosystems,




while at  the same time beginning the process of organizing the  discussion of




methods  of measurement  of the worth of these  benefits.   The  chapter




concludes with  a detailed outline of the plan of the rest of the  study.








           A.   Goods and Services Provided by_ Aquatic Ecosystems






   The steps involved in determining  the economic value of  ecological goods




and  services are to identify what  benefits  ecosystems  provide for  mankind,




to characterize these benefits  in ecological terms, and then to assess their




economic  value.   Even  the  first step should not be thought of as completed




for  any  actual ecosystem.    Indeed,  it  is  virtually certain that as our




understanding  of ecosystems  progresses in the future,  we will discover the




existence of presently  unrecognized goods and services provided  by healthy




ecosystems.  The characterization  of goods  and  services  by ecologists must




include not only a description of the  nature of the good or  service, such as




how many trout for sports fishing  a particular stream maintains, but also




how  the continuing provision of that  benefit is linked to  the future state




of  health of  the  ecosystem.   Generally the ability of ecologists to




characterize the magnitude of the benefit  under ambient  circumstances far




exceeds  their ability  to  assess  how continuing provision  is linked to




environmental quality.   Finally, valuation must take  into  account  not only




the  effect of a  change in environmental quality on  the ability  of an




ecosystem to provide the benefit under discussion, but  also  its effect on






                                     1

-------
the overall health of the ecosystem, which in turn may influence the  future



ability of the system to  provide  benefits  not  presently  identified.    This



"insurance" factor is most difficult of all  to include in the  benefit-cost



calculus because it requires having  to  guess  the  value and the ecological



interconnectedness of benefits  that we have not even  identified as of yet.



   In order  to  guide our thinking  about methods of measuring benefits



we have chosen  to  categorize  the goods and services provided by aquatic




ecosystems as being those for which the environment is  an input,  that is,




the ecosystem provides  a factor or means in the production of a good or



service  to be consumed,  and those for which  the  environment itself  is a



final  good.    This distinction  is,in a sense, artificial, since many goods



and services  provided by aquatic ecosystems fall  in both categories.   It



will,  however,  be useful because, as explained in section  B below and



further in chapter 7,  it  corresponds in some  ways to a distinction between



approaches to economic valuation.








Goods  and Services for  which Aquatic Ecosystems  Provide Inputs  to  the




Production Process





   The most obvious set of goods for which aquatic ecosystems  provide basic



inputs are "fisheries" products.    These products,  as indicated  in  Table 1,



include harvested  fish,  shellfish, and crustaceans;  aquatic plants such as



kelp,  which  is used in the manufacture of  chemicals  and  food products;  and,




to a  small extent, aquatic mammals,  now used mostly for garments.   The



rivers  and reservoirs  that allow hydroelectric production and  its control



contain aquatic ecosystems.   Some types of damage to these ecosystems,  e.g.



siltation  of  reservoirs  caused by soil  erosion and  runoff, can affect  the




output of the hydroelectric system.   Rivers,  lakes,  bays,  and  estuaries are

-------
TABLE 1:  GOODS AND SERVICES PROVIDED BY AQUATIC ECOSYSTEMS


Goods and Services for which the  Environment Provides Inputs

     Fisheries Products:'  Fish, Shellfish, Crustacea, Kelp, Aquatic Mammals

     Hydroelectric Power

     Transportation

     Treatment of Human Wastes

     Treatment of Industrial Wastes

     Water Purification

     Drinking Water Storage

     Information Produced via Scientific Research


Goods and Services for which the  Ecosystem is  a Final Good

     Recreational Use of Aquatic  Areas  (Public Access and Commercial)

          Direct Use  of Water:   Boating,   Rafting,  Sailing,  Canoeing,
                      Scuba-diving,  Swimming,  Wading

          Recreational  Use  of  Aquatic  Organisms:   Fishing,  Waterfowl
                      Hunting, Collection  of Shellfish and Crustacea

          Waterfront Recreational Activities:   Strolling, Hiking, Sunbathing,
                     Team  Sports  (e.g. Volleyball),  Off-Road  Vehicle Use,
                     Horseback Riding,  Nature  Study (e.g. Birdwatching)

     Amenities

          Scenic Values

          Modulation of Local Climates  by  Large Bodies  of Water

          Status and Enjoyment of Owning or  Having  Access to  Aquatic Areas

          Informal Education of Children

          Psychological Benefit of Availabilty of Pristine Areas

     Future Goods and Services

          Preservation of Genetic Information:  Protection of endangered
                     Species, Preservation of  Gene  Pool

          Preservation  of Wild Areas for  Use by Future Generations and for
                     Future High-Value  Development

-------
also used as  transportation arteries,  and  thus provide an  input to the



process of moving people and goods  from place to place.




   An extremely important  and often overlooked set of processes in which



aquatic ecosystems play  roles are  human  and  industrial waste-treatment and



water purification.   When human wastes are discharged into  bodies  of water,



biological and physical processes  combine to break down organic matter and



release nutrients in the wastes, and to kill pathogenic organisms.   In a



similar manner many  industrial  wastes  are  broken down  when  disposed  of in




aquatic  environments.   Coupled with  these  waste-treatment  functions,



wastewaters  disposed  of  in  lakes,  rivers, marshes, and other aquatic areas



are purified and recycled either by evaporation and subsequent precipitation



or by percolation  through benthic (bottom) sediments and  soil to groundwater



aquifers.   Wastewater added to  a lake might undergo biological  treatment by



aerobic (oxygen-using) bacteria associated with oxygen-producing  algae



growing at  the water's  surface,  chemical treatment by entrapment of metals



and  other substances  in  the anaerobic (oxygen-free)  bottom waters and




sediments, and physical treatment by filtering through  sediments and soils




before it reaches a subterranean aquifer  that supplies fresh  water to



consumers.    Properly functioning aquatic ecosystems  in reservoirs also



provide  appropriate conditions  for the  storage of drinking water.   Clean



and/or potable water  is an essential input to the production of a vast



number of products and  services.



   Aquatic environments also provide opportunities for  scientific  research



and  development.   In  this case  knowledge is  the product for  which the



environment is an input.   This knowledge  may  take the  form of information



about  the improved  cultivation of a valuable  organism,  for  example, or



data that enables prediction of the behavior  of other  aquatic ecosystems,



and how the goods  and services  that they provide will  vary under  changing

-------
conditions.   The study  of  one small lake,  for  example, might provide



information valuable  in protecting a number  of lakes in an area from acid



rairi OP  some other pollutant  stress.








Uses of  Aquatic Ecosystems in which the Environment is the "Final Good"






   Perhaps the most  obvious set of goods and services  in which aquatic



ecosystems are in a sense final goods are the recreational uses of  watery



areas.   These recreational goods, as listed  in Table 1, include direct uses



of water, the recreational pursuit and harvest of aquatic organisms, and




waterfront recreational activities.   Examples of activites involving the




direct use of water  are boating,  rafting, sailing, canoeing,  scuba-diving,



swimming, and wading.  Fishing, hunting of waterfowl, and collection of



shellfish and Crustacea  are examples of the recreational use of aquatic




organisms.    Waterfront recreational activities  include  strolling,  hiking,



sunbathing,  sports  such as volleyball,  the use of off-road  vehicles,



horseback riding, and nature study (e.g.  birdwatching).   Many  of the



recreational goods mentioned above  are available  in both  public areas and



through commercial interests such as tourist hotels and lodges close  to the



water, tour boats, and fishing and other guide services.   Virtually all of




these goods and  services depend on good water quality for their value.




    A much more amorphous  class of benefits  provided by aquatic  ecosystems



can be  loosely described as "amenities".   These include the pure scenic



value of a waterfront area  or lake,  the modulation of local climates by



 large bodies of water, and the status and enjoyment provided by owning or




having  access to areas near the water.   While the  practical nature of these



amenities is clear  to everyone, there is a "spiritual" side  to the scenic



 value of aquatic ecosystems that may represent the dominant benefit that

-------
these ecosystems provide.    In the informal education of many children,




nature plays an extremely important role.    From the autobiographies  of




numerous  writers, artists, scientists, and others we read often of how early




exposure  of pristine wildlands shaped these  peoples' minds beneficially.




Such writings reveal the awareness  of ecosystem benefits by those that are




most able to express these experiences  vividly, but these same benefits




accrue, of course, to a  far wider spectrum of  people who are not necessarily




as conscious  of, or articulate about, their existence.




   Beyond the  formative years of childhood, amenity values continue  to




enrich peoples' lives, but in ways  that can be distictly different from the




ways in which children  benefit.   In particular,  a greater awareness of the




amenities occurs as  we  mature and  the experience of nature becomes  less




formative than it  is restorative.   The person in an  office in downtown San




Francisco, for  example, may  take comfort in the fact that pristine areas are




available for him or her to enjoy.    This  thought, that escape from the "rat




race" is possible, may make it easier to live and work happily in a city.




If such  a person were asked  what this amenity  was worth,  he or she might




quote some  figure, but it is  possible, since the  scenic area has always been




available,  that  the  individual  would  undervalue  this amenity  relative  to




what would be considered his or her "share" of the value of the scenic area




to society  as  a whole.




   A final class of goods and services provided by aquatic ecosystems can be




loosely described  as  future goods and  services,  and  the preservation




thereof.   This  includes the  preservation  of diverse genetic  information,




the  preservation of  ecosystems  for  future generations of humans to  enjoy,




and  the  preservation  of  aquatic  areas for  future development.   The




protection of endangered species—for their future commercial  use, aesthetic

-------
value,  use as objects for scientific study, and existence value—is one



example in which  the preservation of genetic  information  can provide future



goods and services for society.    In preserving a diversity of plants and



animals we are also preserving a library of genes that,  with man's growing



ability to manipulate  genomes, may someday become tools useful  in  producing



valuable drugs or chemicals.   The preservation of scenic and wild  areas for




future generations  to  use—our National Parks are examples—provides future



goods and  services in the  form of both recreational  opportunities and



aesthetic values, as described above.  The knowledge that scenic areas will




be available to their  descendants in the  future may also provide the benefit



of peace of mind to a person living today.    Finally,  preservation of some



aquatic areas may  allow them to be developed for high-value uses in the



future.    Mining in a scenic  lake area rich in some ore,  for example, might



have to be done today in such a way that the scenic value  of the place  is




lost indefinitely—through poisoning  of the aquatic ecosystem by acids



leached from mine tailings,  soil erosion  from road constuction,  or physical



rearrangement of the area—but it might be possible to mine the same region



at some future time,  using an as-yet undeveloped technology,  in such a way



that the aesthetic value of the area remains intact.    In  the latter case



the  area continues to  provide  recreational and aesthetic goods  and services



in addition to the valuable ore.   As described  in chapter 5 the presence  of



future-worth  considerations can greatly influence regulatory choices



regarding the control of  pollution  of aquatic ecosystems.








                          B.   Economic Valuation






      As the discussion in the first  part  of  this  chapter has suggested, the



goods and  services that can be provided by aquatic ecosystems  are many and

-------
varied.  Yet for the purpose of characterizing evaluation, we must try to




collect them into a manageable  number of categories, corresponding to




methods of evaluation.   This  we attempt in the table, Table 2, below, with




the hope that  no  major items, at  least,  are  lost in the  process.   Types of




goods  and services are  classified  into those  involving the  aquatic




ecosystem, the environment, as input, and those involving it as a  final good




(or service).  By environment as input, we mean that it enters into a kind




of mixed  biological-economic production function,  along with conventional




inputs such as labor and capital,  to yield  some desired final good—as the




table  suggests,  a  supply  of fresh  water  for drinking,  perhaps,  or a




shellfish harvest.  The consumer of the water, or the shellfish,  is assumed




to care  only about the good he consumes,  and not  the input mix  used to




produce it.  By contrast, when the environment is valued as a  final  good, it




enters directly  into the consumer's utility  function.   Thus improved water




quality  can yield benefits both  as an  input to  some production process, and




directly  to on-site  recreationists, nearby property owners, and so on.




     A couple of more exotic, or less tangible, goods are  also indicated in




the table.  One  is  the conservation of genetic information.  This can be




considered as affecting  future commercial harvesting, for example  of a plant




or anima'l species for some yet-to-be-discovered medicinal property.  The




other  intangible  good  is  the existence  of  an  unspoiled  environment,




unrelated to any use or consumption of its resources now or  in the future.




Some people derive  satisfaction simply  from the knowledge of  existence, and




this has  been termed "existence  value" in the  literature of  environmental




economics.




     Now, why is it sensible to classify the goods and services provided by




aquatic ecosystems in this fashion? Consider  the first column in  the  table,




headed  "method of evaluation."  It is our view that a particular  method can






                                     8

-------
                            TABLE 2:

          METHODS OF VALUATION FOR GOODS AND SERVICES

                 PROVIDED BY AQUATIC  ECOSYSTEMS
     Method of Valuation
    Type of Benefit
Shifting Supply,  Given Demand
Environment as Input

   Water Supply and Quality

   Commercial Harvesting
   (includes genetic conservation
    for future harvest)
         Travel Cost
                                    Environment as Final Good
          Recreation
  Comparative Property Values
           Amenities
    Contingent Valuation
        Existence Value

-------
be identified as best suited  to  each of the  categories.  Thus,  if the




environment  is viewed as an input  to a  production process,  such as the




commercial harvesting of shellfish, an  improvement in quality due to reduced




pollution loadings can be expected to lead to a shift (down and to the




right,  on a conventional diagram) in  the cost or supply  of shellfish.  Given




an independent estimate of the demand for  the  particular  shellfish product,




the shift in  supply generates an increase in  combined consumer  and producer




surplus, the area bounded by  the demand and supply  curves.   Of course,




establishing  the nature of the  connection between reduced pollution and the




supply shift is a difficult empirical problem.  In section A of chapter 7




below  we  consider the problem in some  detail,  and  illustrate our method of




solution  with  some computations based  on  estimates  of  relevant demand and




supply parameters in the  literature.   The  use of a change  in combiend




surplus  to capture the welfare  effect  of  reduced pollution is  justified in




chapter  6, a theoretical discussion of the economic concept of benefit.




     An aquatic ecosystem can also,  as we have noted, be  viewed as an  input




to the generation of fresh water supplies in  a region.   Reducing  pollution




loadings  in  the system similarly results  in a downward  shift in the cost or




supply of providing  fresh  water.   We shall  have more to say about this




contribution  also in  chapter  7.




     Turning   to the environment as final  good,  the  first item  in  our table




 is  recreation.  There is a large literature  on methods  of valuing outdoor



 recreation  resources, discussed in some detail  in section B of chapter 7.




 Here we just note that the preferred method,  rooted  in economic theory  and




 validated in many empirical  applications, is the  travel cost  method.   The




name  is derived from the use  of travel cost  (from the point of visitor




origin to the recreation destination) as the measure of price in an analysis




of the demand for recreation at the site in  question.   Thus our  focus has






                                    10

-------
shifted  from supply to demand.   There  is however an interesting  parallel to




the analysis of the environment as input.  Suppose an improvement in water




quality makes  available a site that  can  be  assumed to perfectly substitute




for another (in  the provision of recreation).  Then recreation at the first




or unimproved  site is iri effect available at lower cost,  to those who  live




nearer the  newly available site. Of course,  this analytical device requires




the assumption that  the newly available  site  provide  the same recreation




services as the other,  so  that consumers are indifferent as  to  which is




chosen as  "input."




     Reducing  pollution in  an aquatic ecosystem can  also  lead to enhanced




amenities.  Clean water  makes nearby residential  property more desirable.




An extensive  literature has  explored the relationship between changes in




environmental  amenities and property values—the extent to which  it  exists,




the  circumstances under which  it  can be  estimated, its  magnitude in



particular cases, and so on.   This literature is  reviewed in section B of




chapter 7.



     We come,  finally, to existence value.  This differs in an important way




from all of the other goods, or benefits, discussed  thus far in that it is




not associated with use of the resources of an ecosystem.   In fact it is




often classified, along with  option value, as an "intrinsic", or non-use




benefit of  preserving or improving an ecosystem.  We shall have more to say




about option value  very shortly.  With respect to  existence value, there is




a double problem for  measurement.   First, one  cannot  measure  units of




consumption (to  which  a value  might  then be imputed).  To some extent this




is true also  for amenities—as in the case of an improved view.  But the




value of the  view may be captured by  a change in property  value, since the




view is associated with a piece of  property,  and property is valued in
                                    11

-------
market transactions.



     The second difficulty in measuring existence value is that it is a pure



public good,  and  one whose consumption is not associated with consumption of



some private good  such as residential  property.  About the only approach




that can be employed here—and has  been,  in a small number of empirical




studies—is  so-called  contingent  valuation.   This  is  simply  asking



individuals what they would be willing to pay for the continued existence of




an area or  species.  The  literature has also  addressed the difficulties with




this approach—the  hypothetical nature of the question,  its unfamiliarity to




respondents,  their  propensity for strategic behavior, and so on.   We  provide



a review with special  reference to the application  to aquatic ecosystems in



section C of chapter 7.



     We mentioned  option value as the other commonly identified non-use



environmental benefit.  Yet it  appears nowhere in our table.   The reason is




that,  in our Judgment,  it is  not a separate  benefit,  corresponding to  a



separate good or service  provided by an aquatic ecosystem.  It is instead an



adjustment, or "correction factor," to an  estimate of any of the other kinds



of benefits listed in  the table,  to  take account of uncertainty about their



future values.   This  is a  complex issue,  however, that  has generated



considerable confusion and controversy in  the literature.  Chapter 5  defines



option  value and some of its properties  in an analysis of the valuation of



pollution control in a  dynamic, uncertain  setting.  Further discussion,



focusing on different concepts  of option  value, is  provided  in chapter 6.
                                    12

-------
                         C.   Plan of the Study




     In  the next chapter we discuss a kind of "quick and  dirty" alternate




approach to  valuation,  the  construction of a suite of indicator  variables




(SIV) that  might be  used  to characterize  the  response  of an  aquatic




ecosystem to reduced  pollution or other disruption.  This chapter includes a




review of what might be termed ecological  scoring  methods, such as the HEP




and HES  systems.  It  also introduces concepts which will be useful  later on.




     Chapter 3 is about one of these:  the dynamics of ecosystem recovery.




A model is developed  that  generates  the often-observed and potentially




important  hysteresis phenomenon,  in which a  recovering ecosystem does not




retrace the path  of its  decline.  The point  of the model is  to  enable




prediction of  the recovery behavior of ecosystem populations in which we are




primarily interested,  higher trophic levels such as  fish, from that of the




much more readily observed lower trophic levels such as  phytoplankton.




Chapter 4 is an analysis of error  propagation in measuring  recovery.  That




is., suppose we are uncertain about the degree  of phytoplankton recovery.




How  does  this translate into uncertainty  about recovery of  the  fish




population?




     Chapters  2,  3 and 4  are  primarily about the behavior of aquatic




ecosystems,  with no  systematic discussion of economic valuation.  In  chapter




5 we begin this discussion. A model  is developed to value the control of




pollution,  taking  account of key features  of  the ecosystem  behavior




discussed in the earlier  chapters:  recovery lags,  irreversibilities, and




uncertainty.   The model does not address the question of how  to  estimate the




different categories of benefits identified in the preceding section (of the




Introduction). This  is the task of chapter  7, divided into three parts,




also noted in the  preceding  section:  the environment as input (water




supply, commercial harvest), the environment as final good (recreation,






                                   13

-------
amenities), and non-use benefits  (existence value).   The discussion of




methods of benefit estimation is preceded, in chapter 6, by a theoretical



analysis of the economic concept of benefit.   Specifically,  we motivate use



of combined consumer and producer surplus as the preferred measure of a



welfare change following an environmental improvement.



     In chapter 8 we  consider appropriate directions for  further work.   Our



present intention is to proceed in two areas: (1) comparative analysis of



models for policy evaluation, and (2) development of a case study.   Both




are elaborated in chapter 8.
                                   14

-------
Chapter 2.    A SUITE OF INDICATOR VARIABLES (SIV) INDEX FOR AN AQUATIC
            ECOSYSTEM
I.  The Need for a SIV-Index
         Assessment of the damage to ecosystems ideally  requires
an accurate and precise measurement of the harmful effects.   The
results of such measurements are needed to establish  a numerical
relationship between pollution and economic damage to the
ecosystem.  Although not often used exactly in  this way  there are
several habitat evaluation procedures available to assess  the
"health or state" of the ecosystem.  These measures include
several separate procedures (see reviews by U.S. Water Research
Council, 1981; Putnam, Hayes, and Bartless, 1983; Canter,  1984)
and cover most types of aquatic ecosystem but focus on streams
and wetlands rather than large lakes, reservoirs, large  rivers,
estuaries or the open ocean.  None of these indices is ideal  but
they have served well in some circumstances, especially  for
evaluation of game habitat used for recreational sport,  for
example, deer hunting.
         Any of these evaluation systems can be used  to  give  a
numerical value for the ecosystem over a sustained period  of
time.  The resulting long-term data base is then used to show if
                                1.

-------
a decline or improvement has occurred.   When compared with an
unaffected or control  ecosystem an ecosystem value can be
expressed as a percentage of the optimum even if the evaluation
procedure does not cover all the period of degradation (or
improvement) of the system.
         Of considerable practical interest is the need for the
maintenance of a complete habi ta t in the kind of restoration that
occurs when sewage or other  wastewaters are cleaned up.  For
example, a relatively simple single parameter (e.g., the fish of
concern) or multiple parameters (e.g.,  the index proposed in this
paper) can be assessed routinely while  habitat evaluations are
extensive, expensive, and one-time measurements.

11.   The Requirements for an ideal index;  Selection of variables
for use  in a SIV index
         There are three main requirements:
         oData must be inexpensive to collect.
         oData must already  be  available for some ecosystems for
         use in trial projects.
         oThe connection between the variable and its biological
         effect must be known from experimental  studies.
         The purpose of a SIV index is  to determine aquatic
ecosystem health over time and/or space.  The choice of variables
can change depending on the  ecosystem chosen.  For example,
dissolved oxygen fluctuations can be deadly in mid-western rivers
                                2.

-------
in summer but the  same  quantity  of waste is unlikely to trouble
the temperate open  ocean.   Since biologically non~functional
variables decrease  the  precision of any index they should only be
used where important.

III.  Review and critique  of ecological indexes which could be
used,to estimate ecosystem health.

Critique of existing habitat and other evaluation procedures  as
applied to aquatic  ecosystems
         Existing  habitat  evaluation methods usually focus on
         o   the physical  structure of the ecosystem -- e.g.,
             stream sinuosity,  mean depth, percentage of cover,
             size  of the lake
         o   indigenous, rare,  or sensitive species, diverse
             species composition, and
         o   maintenance of indigenous (native) sport or game
             species.
         The habitat evaluation  procedures are derived from
common sense evaluations once made by wildlife managers.  The
purpose was usually to  decide what mitigation should be given if
an area was to be  physically destroyed -- as for example if a
housing development or  a dam were to be built in the area.  In
many cases mitigation  was  the creation, donation, or restoration
of a piece of land which was of  comparable ecological worth to
                                3.

-------
that being  destroyed.   An  example  might be  the degradation of a
stream by  treated sewage  could be  compensated for by  the  creation
of a marshland on the  treatment plant property.
         The  evaluation procedures have a  terrestrial  bent (e.g.,
deer, partridge)  since  lakes and streams cover only a  small
portion of  the landscape.   Thus physical features such as trees,
browse, overhanging banks (for fish), are  important,  even
dominant in existing habitat evaluations -- and  rightly so for
terrestrial and some aquatic systems.
         However, most lakes, oceans, estuaries, larger streams,
and rivers  are structured on the basis of  thermal stratification,
the chemical  stratification which  follows,  and an ever-changing
biotic structure.  Wetlands are intermediate in  this  respect
depending on  the  degree of submersion and  the life times  of  the
plants which  constitute the base of the food chain.
         Pollution in  aquatic systems alters the biotic
structure,  sometimes the overall chemical  structure,  but  rarely
the thermal or physical structure  of aquatic ecosystems.   In this
it differs  from terrestrial habital destruction.  The  rebuilding
of a damaged  landscape requires the regrowth of  a complex of
physical habitats, while the restoration of an aquatic one may in
principle require only the cessation of pollution.  In both  cases
it is assumed that the biotic component is  readily available to
migrate in  from adjacent areas.
         Most of  the indices, especially the habitat evaluation
                                4.

-------
procedure (HEP),  the  habitat evaluation system (HES),  and the
ecosystem scoping  method  (ESM),  also  incorporate  an  implicit
(HEP, HES)  or explicit (ESM)  belief  that diversity = stability =
desirability.  That is,  the  more different types  of  organisms
there are (or the  more links there are in the food web)  the
higher the  ecosystem  will  score.  Thus the most valuable
ecosystems  tend to be the  most diverse by this rationale.
         The diversity-stability argument has a 20 year  history
in ecology.   One  might sum up the conclusion as the  relationship
between diversity  and stability depends on the definition of
stability and the  time scale of observation.  For example, if
stability is equated  with  constancy  over time then,  when using
typical northern  temperate human time scales of years  the simple
non-diverse arctic owl-1emming-grass  food chain appears
unstable.  When viewed over decades  the opposite  conclusion can
be drawn (i.e., a  perpetually oscillating population).  Other
definitions of stability can lead to  yet other relationships with
diversity which are not discussed here.  It is unfortunate that
the early discoveries of high diversity in tropical  forests and
coral reefs were  not put in a better  perspective  for seasonally-
controlled temperate-polar systems.
         The intent of this paper is  to review in brief  existing
habitat evaluation procedures and attempt to derive  a
specifically aquatic index which can  be used to describe the
"health" of the ecosystem.  Such an index will be imperfect but
                                5.

-------
is needed if one is to assess change over time, and thus see
effects such as hysteresis•(e.g.,  Edmondson and Litt,  1982, also
see later in this report), improvement, degradation and ascribe
some economic value to the measured changes.
         The choice of variables  for an aquatic health index can,
in theory, be made from any  or all  trophic levels in the
ecosystem.  Unfortunately  the organisms of most direct economic
interest  (recreational or  sports  fish and shellfish) do not seem
to be either easy or inexpensive  to sample or to use for robust
indices.  Because of their size,  relative rarity and biological
complexity fish and shellfish produce variables which  vary widely
from the  mean value.  These  parameters have a high coefficient of
variation and when combined  into  any index these large errors
propagate to the point of  rendering the index useless  for
practical purposes.
          An example of this  is the "scope for growth"  (SFG) index
which has been widely proposed for the assessment of the health
of fish and shellfish.  In a recent (1983-1984) and costly study
of the effects of the large  sewage effluents of Los Angeles, the
California Dept. of Fish and Game (Monterey Office), together
with the  local discharger  and various other regulatory agencies
use  the SFG method.  Analysis of  this data shows that changes
shown near outfalls using  the "scope for growth" (SFG) method are
not  statistically significant.  Both increases and decreases in
SFG  relative to controls occurred at outfalls but similar changes
                                6.

-------
occurred between replicated samples in the same place.   The SFG
method has a  poor and inexplicably variable  precision relative to
other methods of growth measurement.   SFG can only resolve
changes of 282% (average of all Cal-COMP  data)  while simple
measurement of length or weight have  uniform precision  and can
resolve differences of 4% length and  14%  weight (Home, 1984).
         If we are to detect the biological  effects of  pollution
near outfalls, a more precise measurement of mussel growth must
be used to replace scope for growth tests.  Such a precise method
has been developed for Region #2 (San Francisco Bay Regional
Water Quality Control Board) by scientists at the University  of
California, Berkeley.  It is clear that SFG  is  still very much at
the research stage and not a monitoring tool.

Why is the Scope for Growth Test so Imprecise?
         The reasons are both physiological  and statistical and
both are inevitable.  The physiological reason  is that it is
common for organisms moved from field to  laboratory to  experience
long-term stress (see Knight and Foe, report to RWQCB,  1984).
This together with individual genetic variation gives a highly
variable end result.
         An implicit assumption in this method  is that  SFG
represents an obsolute measure of mussel  health.  For example, it
is assumed that "healthy mussels" are always of approximately  40
joules h~l-  Values measured on mussels transplanted to other
                                7.

-------
sites are often much  lower  than  this  due  to transplant effects
alone.   In addition,  spawning  stress  will  reduce growth.   These
stresses and other uncontrolled  variables  reduce the utility of
SFG as  a monitoring tool  to  almost zero.   The statistical  reason
for the low precision of  scope for growth  results from SFG being
a value calculated from a  series  of ratios and assumed values.
Errors  propagate through  such  an  equation.  It is usually  better
to measure a biologically  integrated  change directly -- i.e.,
measure growth directly rather than indirectly.
         The problem  of high variance is  apparently inherent in
these higher trophic  level  indices.  Even  relatively simple
values, such as th'e percentage survival  of animals exposed to  an
environmental pollutant,  can be  variable  since animals which
appear  identical in size,  condition,  and  amount of pollutant
absorbed may have a very  different genetic makeup (Hilvsum, 1983;
Home and Roth, in prep.)
         There are two ways to overcome  this dilemma.  First,
simpler, more abundant organisms  can  be  used to construct  a
robust index.  Second, functional components of one or more
groups  of organisms can be  used  instead  of their abundance.
                               8.

-------
IV.   Proposed Suite  of  Indicator Variables  (SIV)  Index:
strengths,  weaknesses.
         Lacking  any absolute  ideal  indicator(s)  for ecosystem
health an index is  an obvious  second choice.   This  has  a  history
in economics (price  index)  and in ecology  (diversity index,
striped bass index).  Again in common with  economics (consumer
price index) but not usual  in  biology,  an  index with several
components  seems  desirable. The problem with  an  index  based  on
any  one variable  in  ecology is two-fold, lack  of  robustness  and
risk of being misleading.   Over the  last century  several  single
indices have been proposed  as  "master variable".   Acidity (pH)
has  often been proposed (Schindler et al.,  1985)  but is
misleading  for acid  rain studies and alkalinity has been
substituted (Hendriksen, 1979).  While  alkalinity is an
appropriate guide to the susceptibility of  a  lake to acid
oligotrophication (acid-induced impoverishment) it  is not a  good
indicator of the effects of point or non-source wastewater
pollution.
         What is required  is a suite of independent variables
which would, if taken together, reliably show  the current state
of the ecosystem.  Only if  the majority of  variables indicate a
change in the same  direction will there be  good probability  that
the damage  is serious (ecologically  important) and  persistent.
It should be noted  that this majority indicator approachimplies
that the "cost" of  a false  warning is greater  or  equal  to the
                                9.

-------
"cost" of a false assumption that all  is well.   This could be
described in terms of the "crying wolf"  paradox.   It is not usual
to consider the damage done by false warnings of  severe damage.
However, from an ecological viewpoint there is  only a certain
amount of public concern for ecosystem preservation.  Thus false
warnings can detract from the effort required to  respond to true
warnings.  An example of this is the hue and cry  over DDT and its
environmental effects.  The cancers and  genetic damage now
ascribed to PCB are not effects of DDT.   Although there are
serious effects and a ban on DDT use was appropriate the toxicant
PCB was overlooked for many years since  its chromatographic
signature was confused with DDT.  A decade was  lost when PCB-
filled devices could have been phase out.

The plankton
         Large numbers of independent (i.e., physically
unconnected) organisms can be sampled with low  statistical
variance.  For example, counting 100 single-celled free-floating
phytoplankton gives 95% confidence limits of being within +20? of
the true number  (100).  It is not always easy to  be sure one has
overlooked some algae when examining lots of similar-looking
cells.   If a similar number of cells were counted but were
contained in 16 filaments the 95? confidence limit would only be
+50%  -- a much larger error (Land, Kipling, and Le Cren, 1959,
pg. 158).  In addition to counting errors if the  organisms are
                               10.

-------
also physically  well-mixed then genetic variation between
individuals is  muted.   These  conditions are  best met in  the
aquatic ecosystem in that group of organisms called the
plankton.   The  word plankton  means wanderer  and basically refers
to those small  plants  and animals which are  more or less at  the
mercy of water  currents.   In  this paper I  will  use the  term  in
its widest extent to cover small unattached  organisms in ponds,
lakes, streams,  rivers, estuaries, oceans  and coastal fringes
including salt  marshes.  Thus true animal  plankton (zoo-
plankton), plant plankton, (phyto-plankton)  as  -well as  the
invertebrate insect drift in  rivers and streams is encompassed.
         As defined widely plankton includes the young  stages of
almost all the  commercially valuable fish  and shellfish  and  most
of the sport fish and  shellfish.  Those which are not included
depend heavily  on the  plankton for food in the  adult stages.   For
not fully understood evolutionary reasons  the majority  of large
valuable fish and almost all  shellfish need  a planktonic life-
stage and some  such as salmon, dungeness crabs, grey mullet  or
eels  swim or crawl thousands  of miles to achieve this planktonic
goal .

The functional  components of  aquatic ecosystems
         The previously mentioned high variance (= high  risk  of
incorrect predictions) was first recognized  in  the study of
stream benthos  (e.g.,  Wurtz,  1960).  Here  extreme patchiness
                               11.

-------
(large  rock  adjacent to gravel,  sand  etc.)  could only be  overcome
by very large  numbers  of replicate  samples.   Typically 73
replicate collections  in a  stream  riffle  might be needed  for 95%
confidence in  the  numbers of  invertebrates  collected relative to
3-6 replicates which are normally  the limit (Needham and  Usinger,
1956).   This patchiness was  later  found  to  be common in most
aquatic ecosystems and remains  a partially  solved problem
(Richerson,  et al., 1970; Riley, 1976;  Sandusky and Home,  1978).
         In  addition,  particularly  in streams, wetlands,  and
estuarine-ocean systems the  identification  of individual
organisms is often impossible.   The animals in the above-
mentioned ecosystems are numerically  dominated by juvenile  stage
of such groups as  clams, oysters,  polychaetes, insects,  fish and
crabs.   The  taxonomic keys for  juveniles  in many cases have not
yet been written and even when  published  require expert
taxonomists.  This problem was  again  first  tackled by stream
ecologists who proposed to simplify their ecosystem by using
functional group classification instead  of  taxonomic
identification.  Thus shredders, scrapers,  filterers replaced
large crayfish, caddis-flies, and  may-flies even though the
functional classification cut across  traditional taxonomic  lines.
         In  smaller ecosystems  such as  ponds and small streams it
has been possible  to measure whole-ecosystems variables such as
net photosynthesis or respiration  using  whole-lake oxygen fluxes,
isotope dispersion, or even carbon  depletion.  The process  has
                               12

-------
provisionally been extended  to  incorporate large lakes (Tailing,
1976).
         Functional  components  have  the advantage of built-in
robustness since they incorporate  ecosystem homeostasis as
explained below (i.e.,  the intertia  and redundancy in ecosystems
which tend to reduce overall  change).   A typical example of this
would be the replacement of  the attached stream algae Cladophora
by the attached stream  algae  Tabellaria near the inflow of a
well-treated but nutrient-rich  domestic sewage outflow in the
Truckee River, near Lake Tahoe  (Home  et al . ,  1978).  Insect and
presumably fish populations  did not  respond to this food chain
switching presumably because  either  algae was  equally acceptable
(or unacceptable) as food.

Combined plankton-functional  component index -- the SIV index
         For purposes of monitoring  the ecosystem effect of
pollutants a combination of  both the plankton  and functonal
components will be valuable.   Large  numbers of individuals (n)
can be measured which will reduce  type II errors and concomittant
failure to detect pollution's effects  until it is too late.  A
large n will also reduce type I errors and risk of overstating an
effect.  The use of juvenile  stages  of commercially and
recreationally important fish and  shellfish will assist in the
economic analysis and will also include "sensitive" species
(sensu EPA guidelines on NPOES  permits).  Both indigenous and
                               13.

-------
rare species can be  accommodated in such an index.  Finally, the
robustness of the index will  be ensured by incorporation of
ecosystem homeostasis by the  use of functional component
variable s.
         The drawbacks to the SIV index in principle are similar
to those of any other environmental scoping or health assessment
namely:
         o   Require some measurement or knowledge of the
             ecosystem.
         o   Is hard to extrapolate backwards in  time to pre- or
             low-pollution eras.
         o   May miss important effects if one component of the
             index was capable of indicating serious harm but the
             other components lagged behind in their responses.
         The proposed SIV index has the advantage for aquatic
ecosystem pollution studies that these drawbacks  can be minimized
particularly in the cost of data -collection since the precision
of  the  index can be very high.
         The main purpose of  any index is  to show changes over
time or space.  High precision is vital if change is to be
detected  in  time for restorative measures  to be put into effect.

         The literature shows a number of  multi-parameter indices
or  ranking  systems used to measure the "trophic state" of lakes
(i.e.,  their basic fertility  of productivity).  These include
                               14.

-------
those by Lueschow et al,  1970;  Shannon  and  Brezonik,  1972;
McColl,  1972;  Michalski  and  Conroy,  1972;  Sheldon,  1972;
Uttormark and  Wall,  1975;  Carlson,  1977;  and the  EPA's  own
modified index derived  from  an  extensive  study  of 757  specially
selected lakes (See  Hern,  Lambou,  Williams,  and Taylor,  1981).
The SIV  index  does not  attempt  to  improve  these models  especially
those by Carlson 1977 and  Hern  (EPA)  et al., 1981.   Our  purpose
is to extend their use  to  cover both  toxic  and  biostimulatory
effects  of point and non-point  wastewater  discharges  as  well  as
extend coverage beyond  lakes to all  aquatic  ecosystems.
         For example, one  improvement of  the model  suggested  by
EPA (Hern et al., 1981)  to use  chlorophyll  a_ not  nutrient  levels
as a basis for trophic  classification fits  directly into the
functional component mechanism  of  the SIV  index.
         Multi-parameter indices also exist which attempt  to
measure  higher trophic  level productivity  including that of
fish.  This is a measure of  ecosystem "health".  Such  attempts
range from pioneering concepts  such as  those of Thienemann  (1927)
and Rawson (1951) to complex but realistic  simulation  models
(e.g., Steele, 1974; Powell, in press).  A  "rough indicator of
edaphic  (= nutrient) conditions" combined  with  lake bathymetry
(morphological structure)  was the  morphoedaphic index  (MEI) of
Rawson  (1955)  and Ryder (1965)  and Ryder et al. (1974).
         The MEI uses mean depth and fish  harvest statistics  and
was designed for use in lakes.   Since the  most  productive  systems
                               15.

-------
(lakes,  streams,  estuaries  and  coastal  ocean waters)  are shallow
and well-stirred  this  index has limited use when  expanded from
typical  thermally stratified lakes  to all  aquatic ecosystems.
         Complex  simulation models  of the  plank tonic  community
are not yet usable as  indices even  though  multiple parameters  are
involved.  A primary reason is  that such models are not normally
designed to work  with  the kind  of pollution stress normally
imposed by toxic  wastewater.  Typically, the models will be
perterbed by nutrients or the introduction of a natural change
such as increased predation.  Most  chemical poisoning or aquatic
habitat structural alteration has few natural analogs and these
are yet little studied.   The few potential analogous  systems
natural springs with high acidity as toxic metals have been
little studied for metal  toxicity dynamics.  Almost no examples
of organic biocide accumulation are available in  natural aquatic
ecosystems.  However,  metal or  organic toxicants  are  a prime
cause of aquatic ecosystem degredation, second only to dissolved
oxygen reduction  and diversion  of water.
         The construction of a  numerical SIV index with some of
the properties mentioned previously cannot be easily  formulated
in the abstract  (see e.g., Boesch,  1977).   Thus the index must be
built on a case  study  and then  generalized if possible.  The task
is formidable but an equal problem  is acquiring an adequate data
base which would also  be available  for other ecosystems.  Records
of planktonic and other biological  variables are often available
                               16.

-------
in  the open  literature.   In contrast,  pollution  loading  values

are  hard  to  find  over long periods  --  although they are  usually

available  somewhere in  the files of  individual dischargers

(Russel and  Home,  1977)  or in  the  files  of the  local  regulatory

agency (Home,  Fischer  and Roth, 1982).


V.   Summary

     An index which  will measure the health of aquatic  ecosystems would be

very useful in determining  the amount of damage,  or recovery from damage, in

aquatic ecosystems.   The index should ideally be  robust,  precise, and multi-

dimensional and reflect  changes due to either toxicity  or biostimulation.

An  index of selected indicator variables—the SIV index—is  proposed which

builds on the existing EPA  and other indices used to estimate "trophic state".

The  SIV index differs from  the existing habitat evaluation indices in that the

bias is towards aquatic  ecosystems rather than terrestrial ones.  This bias

is  needed since the  damage  caused by humans to the two  habitats  is of a

different kind.  The structure of aquatic ecosystems is dynamic  and is main-

tained  by short-term biological and chemical inputs.  Terrestrial ecosystems

depend  much more on  the  physical structures such  as trees and hills.  Water

pollution  usually destroys the chemical and biological structure while ter-

restrial disruption, such  as  housing developments or dams, destroys the entire

physical structure.

     The SIV  index follows  recent trends to use functional components of the

ecosystem  rather than only  taxonomic classification.  The index  is comprehen-

 sive in  that  it uses both  types of information.  A major  difference from other

 indices  is an emphasis on  precision so that small changes in the health of the

 ecosystem  can be detected  with statistical confidence.  In this  way damage can
                                    17.

-------
be detected before it is too late and recovery techniques modified during
restoration to maximize benefits.  The only way to achieve precision and
avoid both type 1 and type 2 errors is to make a large number of measurements.
This can be done if the variables chosen are inexpensive to measure, and
this concept drives the choice of variables in the SIV index.
     Common, numerous, and functionally important variables would be chosen
for the SIV index.  In most open-water aquatic ecosystems the plankton provide
a good source of information on  the health of the ecosystem.  The plankton
include the young stages of most  commercially and recreationally important
fishes, their food, and the photosynthetic base of the entire food chain.
The plankton are sufficiently numerous and homogeneous to sample at a reasonable
cost and are most directly exposed to water-born pollutants.  For wetlands
and streams the same principles  apply but the collection techniques must
;be modified by the use of analogs to achieve the same high precision at a
comparable cost.
     Future research should focus on long-term data  sets from already damaged
test ecosystems where data are readily available and easily supplemented.
This concept  is opposite of the  NSF long-term research program which considers
only pristine ecosystems.  Thus  data from various  less accessible "grey"
literature will be the  principle source of  information.
                                      18.

-------
                           References

Cantor,  L.W.   1984.   A comparison  of habitat evaluation
         methods.   EPA.   Environmental  Impact Seminar,
         Washington,  D.C.   Feb.  1984.   73 p.
Carlson, R.E.  1977.   A trophic state index for lakes.   Limno1.
         Oceanogr.  22 361-369.
Edmondson, W.T.  and A. Litt.   1982.   Daphnia in Lake
         Washington.   Limnol.  Oceanogs.   27:272-293.
Hendricksen,  A.   1979.  A simple approach for identifying  and
         mea'suring  acidification of  freshwater.  Nature.
         278:542-545.
Hern, S.C., V.W. Lambou,  L.R.  Williams,  and W.D.  Taylor, 1981.
         Modifications of models predicting trophic state  of
         lakes:   adjustment -of models to account for the
         biological  manifestations of nutrients.   (Summary)  U.S.
         EPA  Pb. 81-144 362.
Home, A.J.,  J.C.  Sandusky, J.C. Roth and S.J. McCormick.
         1978.  Biloogical and chemical  conditions in  the  Truckee
         River,  California -- Nevada during the low flow
         conditions of the 1977-8 severe drought.   Rept. to
         McLaren Engineering Co., Sacramento, California.   87  p.
Home, A.J.,  H.B.  Fischer, and J.C.  Roth.   1982.   Proposed
         Monitoring Master Plan for  the San Francisco  Bay-Delta
                               19.

-------
         Aquatic  Habitat  Program.   Calif.  State  Water  Resources
         Board,  Sacramento.   180  p.
Lueschow, L.A.,  J.M.  Helm,  D.R.  Winter,  and  G.W. Karl.   1970.
         Trophic  nature of  sel«cted  Wisconsin  Lakes.   Wise.  Acad,
         Sci.  Arts  Lett.   58:237-264.
Lund,  J.W.G.,  C.  Kipling,  and E.O.  Le  Cren.   1959.   The inverted
         microscope method  of estimating algal  numbers  and the
         statistical  basis  of estimations  by counting.
         Hydrobiologia.   11:143-170.
Michalski, M.F.  and N.  Conroy.   1972.   Water quality
         evaluation.   Lake  Alert study.   Ontario Min. Envir.
         Rep.  23 p.
McColl, R.H.S.  1972.  Chemistry and trophic state of seven  New
         Zealand lakes.   N.Z. J.  Mar.  Freshwat.  Res.   6:399-447.
         Needham, P.R.  and R.L.  Usinger, 1956.   Variability  in
         the macrofauna  of a single riffle in Prosser Creek,
         California,  as  indicated by the Surber sampler.
         Hilgar.dia  24,  14:383-409.
Rawson, D.S. 1955.   Morphometry as  a dominant factor in the
         productivity of  large lakes.   Ve r h. Int. V e r ei n .
         Limnol.   12:164-175.
Richerson, P., R. Armstrong, and C.R.  Goldman {1970).
         Comtemperaneous  disequilibrium, a new hypothesis  to
         explain the "paradox of the plankton."  Proc.  Na tl .
         Acad. Sci.  67:873-880.
                               20.

-------
Riley,  G.A.   1976.   A model  of  phytoplankton patchiness.   L1mno1.
         Oceanogr.   16:453-466.
Russell,  P.P.  and A.  J.  Home,  1977.   The  relationship of
         wastewater chlorination  activity  to Dungeness Crab
         landings in the San Francisco Bay Area.   U.C. Berkeley-
         SERHL Rept.  77-1,  37 p.
Ryder,  R.A., S.A. Kerr,  K.H. Loflus,  and H.A. Regier.  1974.   The
         morphoedaphic index, a  fresh yield estimator -- review
         and evaluation.  J. Fish.  Res.  Bd. Can.   31:663-688.
Sandusky, J.C. and A. J. Home.   1978.  A  pattern analysis of
         Clear Lake phytoplankton.   Limnol. Oceanogr. 23:636-648.
Shannon,  E.E.  and P.L. Brezonik.   1972.   Eutrophication
         analysis:  a multivariate  approach.  J .  S a n i t. E n g.
         Div.   ASCE.   98:37-57.
Sheldon,  A.L.   1972.   A  quantitative  approach to the
         classification  of  inland waters.   pp. 205-261 in Natural
         Environments ed. J. V.Kratilla,  Johns Hopkins Press.
         Baltimore.
Steele, J.H.  1974.  The structure  of marine ecosystems.
         Blackwell, 128  p.
Tailing,  O.F.  1976.  The depletion of carbon dioxide from Lake
         Water by phytoplankton.   J.  Ecol  .  64:79-121.
Wurtz, C.B.   1960.  Quantitative  sampling.  Natil us, 73:131-5.
                               21.

-------
                               CHAPTER 3.






     The Hysteresis Effect in the Recovery of Damaged Aquatic Ecosystems:




            an Ecological Phenomenon with Policy Implications








Abstract




   The individual species or functional components of an ecosystem can be




expected to respond at different rates to the application and/or removal of




pollutant  stress.   These rates are  primarily dependent  on the generation




time (a function of body size and complexity) of the organism and its place




in the trophic hierarchy  (e.g. producer,  grazer or  carnivore).   Even in the




absence of population extinctions, a non-retraceable behavior  (or hysteresis




effect) is  expected. Conceptually,  the lower trophic levels will  follow a




series of nested hysteresis curves,  while  organisms at higher  trophic




levels, such as  sports fish, will probably respond more erratically.  To



explore these issues, we develop an illustrative  hysteresis trophic-link




model (HTLM) that incorporates limited ecological reality but is simple




enough to  expand  to  an  arbitrary number of  functional groups.    This model




is compared to a conceptual model for biotic hysteresis for a system with




three trophic  levels.   We show how hysteresis might influence population




changes at higher trophic levels (e.g. fish) caused by  pollution. These




changes cannot be measured directly because large fish are difficult to




sample with high precision.










Introduction




   In most aquatic ecosystems damage occurs by two mechanisms.    These are




physical destruction (for example, lake edge filling) or chemical perturbation




(notably,  additions  of biostimulants  and  toxicants).   With the exception of






                                     1

-------
sediment  loading, most  pollutants regulated by the  U.S.  Environmental



Protection Agency (EPA) cause damage by chemical perturbation of ecosystems.



   It is often assumed that above  the  dose-response threshold, the change in



some component of an aquatic ecosystem  is linearly proportional to the amount



of pollution,  as for example in the Dillon-Rigler (1974),  Vollenweider (1968),



or Vollenweider and Kerekes (1980) phosphorus- (or nitrogen-) chlorophyll



models of  lake  eutrophication.   Studies on  lake restoration have shown that



non-linearity  and time lags in the recovery of systems perturbed by pollution



occur for at  least some  lakes (e.g. Shagawa Lake,  Maguey et al, 1973; Lake



Washington, Edmondson,  1972).   The  reasons  for non-linearity  have not been



well studied,  but they appear to  be partially  due  to the varying "turnover-



times" of the  physical, abiotic, and simple biotic components of a complete



aquatic ecosystem (Edmondson, 1982;  Home, unpublished).    Further step-



function-type responses and time lags may be introduced  by  "higher-order



interactions"  that occur  far from the site of the pollutant action.   Examples



of these interactions are species displacement such  as occured for lake trout



in the Great Lakes, or indirect competition from changes  in  species dominance



(Christie, 1971).   Given these complications, it is not surprising that the



recovery of an ecosystem's more  complex  biotic levels, such as that of a



damaged  sports  fishery,  does not  proceed  either in a simple  linear or



virtually instantaneous manner upon removal of a pollutant load.



   It is  important to distinguish  between  the purely phyBiochemical  and the



biotic responses to  removal of a  pollutant  from an aquatic  ecosystem.   All



pollutants will decrease when  the  source is shut off and the internal



pollutant load  is diluted as new clean water flushes out  the  system.   In many



cases the pollutant load will  be negligible in months or years—as is  the case



following the  onset of phosphorus  removal  by new sewage-treatment plants



(Goldman and Home, 1983, pp. 392-4).    In any event  the physiochemical

-------
response is generally predictable from a knowledge of the pollutant, the



hydraulic  residence time  in  the system,  the  mean  depth,  and  the



characteristics of the bottom  sediment.



 '  In contrast, the biotic response may be delayed  or may occur in spurts.



In extreme cases the biota may never return to their original states.   The



time path  of  ecosystem recovery  is  not  predictable at present since the



reasons for non-linearity are unclear.    The response  of the  biota to a



decrease in pollution may also fail to mirror the response of the system to



the  original  increase in  pollution,  that is,  the response may  be non-



retraceable.    This paper attempts  to provide  a theoretical  basis for a



mathematical  description  of the biotic  restoration of damaged  aquatic



ecosystems.    In particular  the non-linear and non-retracable character  of the



process of recovery from  pollution—defined  here  as  the hysteresis  effect—



will be considered.



   In the  following sections  we present the general  methods and theoretical



basis for the  hysteresis trophic-link model  (HTLM), describe in a theoretical



way  our  concepts of  "ideal" and  "non-ideal" biotic  hysteresis,  show the



specific form  used  for the HTLM and some initial  results  from the modelling



effort, and discuss the merits and  drawbacks of the HTLM approach  in providing



information useful in setting environmental policy.



Methods and Theoretical Basis





   Time  lag effects may  have many sources, but it is most logical (in the



sense of Occam's  razor) to examine first the turnover time of  the  components



of the ecosystem  as a  possible source.   If a population is to recover quickly



when the pollutant  load is removed it must grow and breed quickly.   Since the



larger organisms depend on  the  smaller ones as food  sources,  populations of



larger organisms cannot grow until populations of smaller organisms are in

-------
place.   The turnover time for biota is usually the generation time and can



range from a few hours for simple bacteria and algae to decades  for very  large



fish such as  striped bass or sturgeon.    Generation time is  primarily a



function of  two  variables:  the sexuality of reproduction  and  the structural
 •


complexity  of  the adults.    Asexual  reproduction (vegetative  or



parthenogenetic reproduction) is typical of simple animals  and  plants growing



under favorable conditions.   Sexual reproduction is  typical of more complex



organisms or of simple ones growing  under  unfavorable conditions.    Sexual



reprodiction uses more time than asexual reproduction, and confers few, if



any, short-term  benefits.    In addition, complex  organisms  must spend time in



building their large complex body structures.   This involves several moults,



a long adolescence, and differing environmental  requirements  for adult and



young,  depending on the  species involved.   The organisms  in the trophic



levels usually present  in aquatic ecosystems have  the  following typical



characteristic sizes  (length,  1) and generation  times (gt)t



     phytoplankton           1  = 0.02 mm,         gt  = 3 days



     zooplankton            1  = 1  mm,            gt  = 3 weeks



     ichthyoplankton         1=1  cm,            gt  = 1 year



     Juvenile piscivorous

     and planktivoral adult  1  s 5  cm,            gt  = 1 year

     fish



     piscivorous fish        1  = 20 cm,           gt  = 3 years



     large sports fish       1  s 50 cm,           gt  = 10  years.



    The  aquatic ecosystem  we use in  our model is  simplified in  the sense that



side,  across, and multiple-step  (omnivory) food-chain  links are omitted



(Figure 1).   Although this may seem  like a major simplification  when one



considers the apparently  highly cross-linked structure of some aquatic food



webs (e.g.  Figure 2), the dynamics of many food webs  are in  fact much less



cross-linked,  in terms of energy or food  flow,  than they appear  to be.    This

-------
                       P2 X2
Figure 1.    Schematic diagram of a trophic-link model.   Here P describes
             the effect of the pollutant  on each trophic level, and X is a
             measure of the biomass present for each functional class of
             organism  (e.g.  primary  producers,  filter-feeders,  carnivores,
             etc.).
                        Inorgimc
                        nuuitnts.
                        t.J.. NO,. CO,
                        CO,. SO.
 Figure 2.     A qualitative food web for the Truckee  River, California.
              Solid lines Indicate measured pathways.    Broken lines are
              assumed  pathways derived  from other  studies  of  adjacent
              waters.    Note  that  the omnivorous feeders (e.g.  dace,  trout,
              sculpin)  use  more than  one trophic level.   Most herbivores
              prefer microscopic  diatoms to large filamentous green and
              blue-green algae.  (Reproduced  from Goldman and Home,  1983)

-------
is illustrated by one of the few known quantitative examples of an aquatic


food chain, that of the River Thames below Rennet mouth (Goldman and  Home,


19&3)>    Figure 3a shows the complete food web for the Thames system.    As

complicated  as this  looks,  placing of the  organisms in  this web  into
 t

functional groups results in the much more simplified structure shown in

Figure  3b.    Thus while the assumption of a  linear  food chain is certainly a

simplification, it may not be a bad  starting point for modelling some aquatic

ecosystems.


   In the linear food chain  depicted in  Figure 1, the rate of change of the


phytoplankton population can  be described  by  the equation



              dX
  (D         ~ - rx (x)(1  -  (X/KX)) - BxyXY   - bxX, where
              dt

          X = the population density of phytoplankton (e.g. chlorophyll a
              per cubic meter of water),


          rx  = the maximal growth rate of the phytoplankton population,

          K   = a carrying capacity constant,


          Bxy = a rate constant describing predation of zooplankton on
                 phytoplankton,

          Y  s the population  of  zooplankton that feed on the  phytoplankton
               (X), and


          bx  = the rate of loss of phytoplankton due to washout and other
               linear, donor-controlled mechanisms.



   In this system we assume that each organism eaten is killed and that no

significant amount of prey is uneaten.


   Analogous equations can be used  to  describe  the rate of change  of the

higher trophic-level  populations.   For example:

-------
Figure  3a.
                                   Light   Suspended
                                  729.000 organic matter
                                                                   C, +H
This figure presents a dynamic food web for a natural system:
an energy flowchart for  the River Thames below Rennet mouth.
In  general,  primary producers are  shown at  the bottom,
invertebrate animals at the center, and fish at the top of the
chart, but  to avoid  complex networks of arrows sources of
attached algae,  detritus, and al lochthonous materials are
shown in two  places.   Heavy  arrows indicate  the largest
channels of energy flow.    Note the twin flow of energy to
fish from low-quality attached  algae and  high-quality  animal
food from terrestrial insects and adult chironomids.    Energy
input from  dissolves organic matter was not measured directly.
(Redrawn from Mann et al,  1972,  reproduced from Goldman and
Home,  1983)
                          Fish (2 species)
       Free-floating
Figure 3b.
                                                 Top
                                              Carnivore
                                                Saall
                                              Carnivores
                                              Herbivores
                                               Producers
                                                (Plants)
                                                              Light +
                                                              Nutrients
The major energetic pathways  from  figure  3a.   This diagram
 shows  that  modeling using single-link  trophic models  is
 possible if the organisms in the ecosystem are classified
 into functional  rather than taxonomic groups.
                                     Attached

-------
             dY

  (2)         — =  ExyBxyX* - ByZTZ - byY, where
             dt



         X, I,  and  B^ are aa above,


         ^xy = a factor  describing the proportion  of biomass consumed from
              trophic  level x (phytoplankton) that is retained in trophic
              level 7 (zooplankton),


         By2  =  a  rate constant describing  predation on zooplankton by
                 icthyoplankton (small fish that feed  on zooplankton),

         Z s the population of icthoplankton, and

         jj_ = the loss rate of zooplankton due to  washout, death, or other
              donor-related mechanisms.

   This pair  of equations can  be expanded to  an arbitrarily large  set

describing an arbitrarily long food chain.

   Changes in pollution will affect some of the growth rates directly, but  all

populations  will be  affected as a  result of trophic interactions.    A

straightforward example of such an interaction is the following. Suppose a


pollutant acted so as to  decrease the growth rate (r*)  of tne phytoplankton in

an aquatic  ecosystem.   This pollutant could be toxic  to the phytoplankton or


could  be an inert  pollutant, like  silt in a  lake,  that  affects  rx by

decreasing  the light available for photosynthesis.    In either case, a

reduction  in the phytoplankton  growth rate  reduces  the  phytoplankton

population, which reduces the amount of food available to the zooplankton,

which reduces the zooplankton population, which reduces the amount of food

available for small  fish, and  so on.   Alternatively, a pollutant may cause an

overall increase in total phytoplankton (e.g. through eutrophication)  but

bring about a decrease in zooplankton levels by allowing undesirable  algal

species  to  dominate at  the expense of species that serve as food for  the

zooplankton.       In this paper we  have  used mathematical relationships like

those  described above to generate a series of "hysteresis relationships"

-------
charting the response of each trophic level in a hypothetical three-level



aquatic food chain to the pollution  and subsequent clean-up of the  ecosystem.





   We have  also assumed,  in making our  calculations,  that the onset  of



pollution and its clean-up are instantaneous.    This is perhaps appropriate



for longer-lived organisms such as  fish,  but has  some inappropriate features



for algae,  which turnover rapidly and thus may respond to intermediate  as well



as initial  and  final  levels of the  pollutant.    If it proves important to do



so, a gradual change  in pollution may be modeled  in  future work, but for our



initial analysis  the  step-function  approach  is  more  enlightening  and



expedient.





Biotic Hysteresis; Theoretical Concept



   The  ecological hysteresis response  will resemble the physical hysteresis



effect observed in the magnetization of a ferromagnet.  When a magnet is



placed next to an unmagnetized bar of iron, the  latter becomes magnetized.



When  the first  magnet  is  taken away,  the  iron  bar  loses its magnetic



properties  much more slowly  than  it gained them.   Similarly,  as the  level of



pollution in an aquatic ecosystem is decreased,  the biological response to the



decrease does not trace out in reverse  the  path it followed in response to the



initial pollution of the system.   Nevertheless,  ideally,  the system, returns



to its starting point.    For the  purposes of this  paper we define "ideal"



biotic hysteresis to occur when  a population  of  organisms perturbed  by



pollution returns to its initial  population  level within  a period of time



short  enough to be relevant to policy decisions.   This time period might be



10 to  20 years.    In an ecosystem with several  trophic levels (phytoplankton,



large  zooplankton and small fish, and  large fish, i.e. producers, grazers, and



large  carnivores) and a  single type of pollutant  (such as sewage)  a series of



response-and-recovery  curves  such  as those shown in  Figure 4 would  be

-------
     100 P
   p
   E
   R
   C
   E
   N
   T

   O
   F

   R
   E
   S
   P
   O
   N
   S
   E
80  -
60  -
40  -
20  -
                                    TIME
Figure  4.   A theoretical distribution of ideal hysteresis curves for an
             aquatic ecosystem with three trophic levels.    Curves marked
             B1"  represent the time-path of the response of a population in
             a lower trophic level (e.g.  phytoplankton)  to a pollutant
             stress and  the path of recovery  once the stress has been
             removed.    "Response" paths  are marked  with left-to-right
             arrows, while "recovery" paths are  indicated by right-to-left
             arrows.    Curves marked "2" and  "3"  represent time-paths  for
             middle (e.g.  zooplankton) and  higher (e.g.  fish)  trophic
             levels,  respectively.    Note that populations in higher
             trophic  levels exibit  greater  lags  in  both response  and
             recovery than those  in  lower trophic levels.
                                   10

-------
expected.   Even the rapidly growning phytoplankton (generation time 1-10

days)  can exibit an ideal hysteresis  response to the  pollutant.   For higher

trophic  levels (copepod zooplankton  and  fish),  which respond to the altered

phytoplankton population, there will be a delay in the initiation of the

exponential  section of the curve  in Figure 4 in rough proportion to the

generation  time.   A delay must occur because complex  organisms are incapable

of rapidly increasing their number (that  is,  they  have a slow numerical

response) on a time scale of days.   It will thus take at  least the adult-to-

birth-to-juvenile  period before  copepods or small fish can show any numerical

response to  the perturbation,  and this response  period will be slightly

shorter than the complete  generation time.    This  lag  in response has the

interesting  consequence that the last half of the change will  occur more

rapidly for high than for low trophic  levels.   Such rapid changes would be of

serious concern to resource managers since  the  response of pollution-control

agencies may be  too  late to protect the  resource before  the  numbers of

important organisms are seriously depleted.    These rapid changes do in fact

seem to happen (see Goldman  and Home, 1983).   Concern about such changes is

compounded by the fact that it  is difficult to measure changes in biomass

stocks at higher  trophic levels, such as fish.    The statistical resolution

for fish stock estimation is usually so poor  that  the majority of a fish

population can be lost before biologists can  detect the  change with any

certainty.

   The ideal hysteresis effect  is characterized by a cyclic  (on a  10-20 year

time scale)  non-retracable  path when the response of  organisms* to pollution
 In figures 4 and 5  the response of each trophic level is normalized so that
 the "percent response" at each time point is given as a percentage of the
 difference between the population of the organism before  the system was
 perturbed and the population at the  point where the pollutant is removed.
 Thus  these curves  show increasingly lagged responses and recoveries from
 pollutant stresses,  but  do not reflect the relative magnitudes  of the
 responses to pollution that might be  shown by the different trophic levels.


                                    11

-------
     100
   p
   E
   R
   C
   E
   N
   T

   O
   F
   E
   S
   P
   O
   N
   S
   E
80
60
      40
20
                                    TIME
Figure 5.    A theoretical distribution of  non-ideal  hysteresis curves for
              an aquatic ecosystem with  three trophic  levels.   Curves
              marked  "1" represent  the time-path of the  response  of a
              population in a lower trophic level  (e.g. phytoplankton) to a
              pollutant  stress and the path of recovery once  the stress has
              been removed.    "Response" paths  are marked with left-to-right
              arrows,  while "recovery" paths are indicated by right-to-left
              arrows.     Curves marked "2"  and "3"  represent  time-paths for
              middle  (e.g.  zooplankton)  and  higher (e.g.   fish)  trophic
              levels,  respectively.  In   this  case,  unlike  the  ideal
              theoretical case presented in  figure U, the  populations do not
              recover completely within  a recovery period of  the  same
              duration as the  original stress.
                                    12

-------
is plotted against  time for a regime in which a pollutant is added (left-to-


right paths in figures U and 5) then removed (right-to-left paths).    A damped


hysteresis effect is also possible.   This  effect, which we have termed "non-


ideal" biotic hysteresis, is characterized by non-retracable and non-cyclic
 •

behavior (as shown in figure 5), is also possible.   A possible explanation  of


such  behavior for  a  specific  food chain  (rather than  a food  chain  of


generalized  trophic levels) is  the following.   If a species of plant  or


animal remains at depressed  levels (e.g. as a  result of  a  pollutant-related


stress)  for  long periods there is in effect a vacant niche that can  be


occupied by a  pollution-tolerant  species or even another species that has  no


direct effect on the  fish  of concern (Christie,  1971).   Generally the


replacement  species are  less highly regarded by sports and/or commercial


fisheries groups  and are an economically inferior substitute for the original


species.    Thus if  the return leg of the hysteresis  curve is very flat after


cessation of pollution, organisms at the valuable higher trophic level may  be


subject  to "species replacement" or "competitive  displacement" and never
                                                     •4

return to their original dominant position.



Methods and Initial Results  from the Hysteresis Trophic-Link Model (HTLM)


   Our objective in this modeling effort  was to test a simple approach for


describing mathematically the hysteresis phenomenon discussed  above.   The


purpose of the model described here is  solely to illustrate  how a generalized


ecological phenomenon of interest (hysteresis)  can be demonstrated using


mathematical  relationships containing easily  identifiable and understandable


parameters.    In this approach a  food chain with three trophic levels—


phytoplankton, zooplankton, and  small  fish—was assumed.   The  rate of change


of  the populations in the  first two trophic levels were  described  by


differential equations  (1)  and (2) above,  and the  rate of change of the
                                    13

-------
population in the third trophic  level was described by








                        dZ


  (3)                   — r EyzByZYZ - bzZ,   where

                        dt
 •


          Y, Z, and Byz are ag previously described,



          E   s that fraction  of biomass  in the  Yth trophic  level that

                 becomes incorporated in the Zth level, and






          bz =  a  rate constant describing the loss  of small fish due  to

                 old-age death and other donor-controlled mechanisms.





   The constants  in  the  three equations were obtained by assuming a value of




0.1 for Exy and Eyz> and a value of 2 x X* for Kx.   The values for  X», Y»,



and  Z*, the steady-state biomass populations for the three  trophic  levels



(that  is,  the  relative amounts of per-unit-area biomass for which dX/dt,



dY/dt.  and dZ/dt  =  0)  were  taken to be  50,   10,  and  1,   respectively.



Generation times for the three  trophic  levels (Tx> T   an(j xz) were  taken to



be 3, 20, and 360 days, respectively.   The following relationships were  used



to derive the values of rx>  Bxy, and By2:




                                rx = Tx"1>



                             ExyBxyX» = Ty'1,



                             EyZByzY» = Tsf1-



values for bx> by and bz were derived from the steady-state forms of equations



(1)  through (3).



   Equations  (1) through (3)  were  incorporated  into a fortran computer



program, which was  used  to approximate the  time path  of populations X, Y, and




Z  in response to a perturbation in  rx> tne phytoplankton.    The program calls



the  NAG (Numerical  Algorithms Group,  1984)  subroutine  D02EBF, which integrates



systems of differential equations  using  a  variable-order,  variable-step  Gear



method and returns solutions  to the system (X(t), Y(t), Z(t)) at specified

-------
time points.   Details of the model and a  listing of the integration program


are given in  the appendix to this paper.


   We should note that  an analytical approximation to  the solution of


equations (1) - (3) can be obtained by  adding a  fouth equation, namely
 •



                                drx
  (U)                           	= 0

                                 dt


to the system, deriving a 4 x 4  "community matrix" using procedures described


by May (1973) and Harte (1985), and using that  matrix to explore the effects


of perturbations  to  the  system.   A  four-level food-chain model  was also


developed.   This  model,  which adds a larger piscivorous  fish to the three-


tiered  food  chain, uses equations (1)  - (3)» above, with the  term   -  BzfzF


added to equation  (3). A fourth equation,


                           dF

  (5)                      — = E2fBzfZF - bfF-
                           dt




is added to model  the behavior of the  population of  larger fish  (F).   In this


system the steady-state biomass  ratios in the four trophic  levels were taken


to  be 500 :  100 : 10 : 1  (X*  :  I* : Z*:  F*),  the  generation  time for the



larger fish (Tf)  was taken to  be 1080 days,  Ezf was  taken to be 0.1, and


E2fBzfZ*F* was defined to equal  Tj.~l.    This four-level system was solved as


above.    Details  of  the model and a listing of the computer program used to


solve it are given in the appendix.




Results


   The  time  paths traced  by the three "populations" (here  taken to mean


biomass  present  in each trophic  level per unit area  of  water) following a -2J


reduction in rx  are shown in figure 6.   The population  of phytoplankton drops


rapidly in response to the reduction in its growth rate,  reaching a  local
                                    15

-------
p
E
R
C 100
E
N
T

0
p 90


0
R
I
? 80
I
N
A
L
P 70
0
P
60



t 	 	 — - 	 , 	 	
X 	 ""' 	 	 — 	
\
\
\
\
\
\
\
X
X
N.
^^
>.
^
^^
*^
»^. 1>>^
"*•-. ^^
"~~" — «.

II 1 1 1 1
                2000
4000       6000

  TIME IN DAYS
8000
10000
Figure  6.     Calculated time paths for the response of the populations
             (measured In blomass per unit area,  Initial biomass ratios:
             50  phytoplankton:  10 zooplankton :  1 small  fish)  in  a
             three-tiered  aquatic food chain to a  -2%  change in the growth
             rate of phytoplankton.  Solid,  dotted,  and  (partially) dashed
             lines give  the  paths  for phytoplankton, zooplankton , and
             small fish,  respectively.  Note that  the  lower trophic levels
             respond  more quickly to the stress than  higher trophic levels,
             but the  ultimate effect on higher trophic  levels is greater in
             magnitude.
                                   16

-------
minimum in 20 days (not visible in figure 6 due to the length of the time



scale).   Thereafter the population  rises quickly, then falls  slowly in



response  to the changes in the  population of its predator (zooplankton).   By



the time  10,000  days (about  30 years)  have  elapsed, the  phytoplankton



population reaches a  steady-state  value equal to 99J of its  original  level.



The population of zooplankton drops more slowly,  but over a  longer period.



For this  second  trophic  level the  maximum deviation from the original



population,  -3-5J,  occurs after  150 days.    From there the zooplankton



population rises to a level about 1£ above that originally  present.   The



population of small  fish declines more  slowly than those of either  of the



lower trophic levels, but in time exibits a greater  response,  reaching a new



steady-state  population 70% as large as the original group.    Note that the



deviations in the  zooplankton and  fish populations are out  of  phase with each



other.   This makes sense ecologically as well as mathematically: as fish



populations decline,  grazing pressure on zooplankton is decreased, allowing



that population to expand.  Perhaps the most important result  shown in  figure



6, however, is that a small (-19) perturbation in the phytoplankton  growth



rate produces a  large (-30t) change  in the  population at the  highest  trophic



level.



   Figures 7-10 present time paths for the three populations in which a -2%




perturbation in rx is applied  at time zero, then removed at  300,  500, 2000,



and  10,000 days,  respectively.   Paths for which arrows point left-to-right



chart the response of the three populations to the original perturbation,



while paths with  right-left arrows chart  the  return paths for  time periods of



the same duration as the  original perturbation.    Thus in  figure  7, for



example,  the solid curve  labeled with a right-pointing arrow  charts the



response of the phytoplankton population to a perturbation applied for 300



days, while the solid path labeled with a left-pointing arrow charts the level





                                   17

-------
  106


P
E
R 104
C
E
N
T
  102
0
F
R
1
G
1
N
A.
L
  loo
    98
 P
 0  96
 P
    94
                                           JL
                50
                        100      150      200

                             TIME IN DAYS
                                                   250
300
  Figure 7 Calculated time paths  for  the response and  recovery of the
               populations  (measured in biomass  per unit area,  initial
               biomass ratios:  50 phytoplankton: 10 zooplankton : 1 small
               fish)  in  a three-tiered aquatic  food chain  when  a  -2t
               perturbation in the phytoplankton growth rate is applied at
               time zero, then removed after 300 days.     "Response" paths
               are indicated  by right-pointing arrows,  and "recovery" paths
               are marked with  left-pointing arrows.   Solid,  dotted, and
               (partially) dashed lines give the paths for phytoplankton,
               zooplankton ,  and small  fish, respectively.   Note  that the
               population of small fish  continues to decline even after the
               perturbation is removed,  and fails to return to  its  original
               position after 300 days of recovery.
                                     18

-------
p
E
R 104
C
E
N
T
102
0
F
f\
° 100
Xt
I
G
I
N 98
A
L
P
One
yb
P
94



—




-

— /A
	 T?. 	 r/ \
r_ 	 -^s \
\\ /?~ ^^
\'-/s "*"' — '•*».
^^v ^""^^"*^^-^
*^^^
"^•^^
^"^^^
	 — *• "--^
~ ' " 	 >

1 1 1 1 1 1
0 100 200 300 400 50(
                           TIME IN DAYS
Figure  8 Calculated  time paths for the  response  and recovery  of  the
             populations  (measured  in  biomass per  unit area, initial
             biomass ratios:   50 phytoplankton: 10 zooplankton :  1 small
             fish)  in  a  three-tiered  aquatic  food chain  when a  -2J
             perturbation in the phytoplankton growth rate is applied at
             time zero,  then  removed after 500 days.    "Response" paths
             are indicated  by right-pointing arrows,  and  "recovery" paths
             are marked with left-pointing arrows.  Solid,  dotted,  and
             (partially) dashed lines give the paths for phytoplankton,
             zooplankton  ,  and small  fish,  respectively.    Note that the
             population of  small fish shows a lag of approximately 50 days
             before beginning its recovery.
                                   19

-------
 p
 E
 R
 C
 E
 N
 T

 0
 F
105
100
   95
R
I
G
I
N 90
A
L


0  85
P
   BO
                   500
                               1000

                            TIME IN DAYS
                                          1500
                                                       8000
 Figure 9 Calculated time paths for the  response  and recovery of  the
              populations  (measured  in  biomass per  unit area, initial
              biomass ratios:  50 phytoplankton: 10 zooplankton : 1 small
              fish)  in  a  three-tiered  aquatic  food chain  when  a  -2?
              perturbation in the phytoplankton growth rate is applied at
              time zero, then  removed after 2000 days.   "Response" paths
              are indicated  by right-pointing  arrows,  and  "recovery"  paths
              are marked with left-pointing  arrows.  Solid,  dotted,  and
              (partially) dashed lines give the paths for phytoplankton,
              zooplankton  ,  and  small  fish, respectively.    Note that  the
              population  of small fish fails  to  return to its Initial
              level after 2000 days of  recovery.
                                    20

-------
  110  U
p
E
R
C
E
N
T
100
0
F  90

0
R
I
   80  -
N
A
L

P  70
0
P
   60
               2000
                        4000       6000

                         TIME IN DAYS
                                               6000
10000
Figure 10 Calculated  time  paths for the response  and  recovery of  the
             populations (measured  in  biomass per unit  area,  Initial
             biomass ratios:  50 phytoplankton: 10 zooplankton : 1 small
             fish) in  a  three-tiered  aquatic food  chain when  a  -2f
             perturbation in the phytoplankton growth rate is applied at
             time zero,then removed after 10,000 days.    "Response" paths
             are indicated by right-pointing  arrows, and "recovery"  paths
             are marked with left-pointing arrows.  Solid, dotted,  and
             (partially) dashed lines give the paths for phytoplankton,
             zooplankton  , and small fish,  respectively.    Note  that  the
             population  of small fish  fails  to  return to its initial
             level even after  10,000 days of recovery.
                                  21

-------
of the phytoplankton population  after the perturbation  is removed.    For  the



return paths time runs right-to-left, thus the points on the return paths



directly above "SO" on the time axis are actually 250 days from the point



where the perturbation was removed.   The presentation of the hysteresis



curves in figures 7-10 are different from those in figures 4 and 5 in that



they  are not normalized to  the  response  of each population to the



perturbation,  rather  they  indicate the percentage change in each population.



This allows  the relative magnitudes of the population changes in the different



trophic levels as well as  the shapes of the hysteresis curves to be compared.



   Figures 7-10 present a series of hysteresis curves in which time paths



for the fish populations  show a progression from non-ideal- toward  ideal-



hysteresis  behavior, as  those terms are defined above.   For  each time



interval the phytoplankton population can be seen, after perturbation of the



system, to decline rapidly to  Just above 98J of its original level, remaining



near  that value  for the duration of the  perturbation.  When the  stress is



removed, the phytoplankton  population quickly increases  to  2%  over its  pre-



perturbation level, then declines to its original level and remains relatively



stable thereafter.    In  each of figures 7-10 the zooplankton population



decreases rapidly following perturbation, then drifts  slowly higher as  fish



populations decline.    When the  perturbation  is removed  zooplankton quickly



increase, due to the increased availability of phytoplankton,  then decline



slowly to near their original  level as fish populations increase.    The



population of  fish shows  a  slow and steady  decline  over a 300-day



perturbation.    The  decline  continues for about 150 days after  the



perturbation is  removed.   In figure 8,  the fish population again  declines



throughout  the perturbation period and  into the return period,  but starts to



recover approximately 50 days after the  perturbation is removed.   Figure 9



shows even less lag before the fish population  starts to recover.   Figures 7-





                                   22

-------
10 show ideal  biotic hysteresis behavior  for the populations in the two  lower



trophic levels, which  return to roughly their original  values.    Note,



however, that even in this case, where a recovery period of 10,000 days is



allowed, the fish population does not quite return to its original level.



   These results suggest the following conclusions.   First, organisms at



higher trophic levels show responses to perturbation of  the ecosystem that are



less immediate but  greater in relative magnitude than the responses of  lower



trophic-level organisms.    Second,  organisms at higher trophic levels exibit



a more  pronounced  lag  in  recovery  from stress  once the perturbation is



removed.   This  lag has ecological importance beyond what we have been  able to



include in our modelling effort, as  a period  in which the population of an



organism is low may provide  an opportunity for another organism,  quite  often



one that is economically less desirable,  to come  in and occupy the former's



ecological niche.



   Thus far the three-tiered ecosystem has been challenged with only a -2%



reduction in the phytoplankton growth rate.   Figure  11 shows the response of



the system over the 3000 days  following a "25% perturbation in r     jn this



case, the population of  small  fish declines to less than 10f of its original



level.   After  the perturbation is removed, the fish population slowly



increases,  but remains at less  than  10f of its original level even after 2000



days.   If the system is allowed 10,000  days of recovery following a 3000-day



-25% perturbation in rx» tne population of small fish gradually rises to 38%



of its original level,  still  ow enough to constitute an example of non-ideal



biotic hysteresis.    It is  probable that in a real system a sustained 90%—or



even  60%—reduction in a fish  species would  result in another,  perhaps less



desirable, species occupying its ecological  niche.    This means that some



component of  an aquatic ecosystem  may never recover from a stress,  even if
                                    23

-------
p
£
R 100
r
\^
E
N
T BO
0
F
0 80
R
1
G
I
N 40
A
L
p
b 20
P
0
«•

*9
\ — =^ 	 A

\
\
\
\
\
\ 	 	 ^ 	 :
\
\
N
\
\
\
Xx
\
^^>
^^^
	 ^^^^__
+ \ 1 1 1 1 1


















0 500 1000 1500 2000 2500 3000
                           TIME IN DAYS
Figure 11 Calculated  time paths for the response  and recovery  of  the
             populations  (measured  in  biomass per  unit area, initial
             biomass ratios:  50 phytoplankton: 10 zooplankton : 1 small
             fish) in  a three-tiered  aquatic food  chain when  a -25%
             perturbation in the phytoplankton growth rate is applied at
             time  zero, then removed after 3000 days.   "Response" paths
             are indicated  by  right-pointing arrows,  and  "recovery" paths
             are marked with left-pointing arrows.  Solid,  dotted,  and
             (partially) dashed lines give the paths for phytoplankton,
             zooplankton ,  and small fish,  respectively.    Note that  the
             population of  small fish falls  to  a critical level and falls
             to return  to its initial level after 3000 days of  recovery.

-------
some fraction of the population remains after the stress is removed.
   Figure 12 illustrates that assumptions as  to the  shape of the "biomass
pyramid"—that  is,  the ratios  of biomass-per-unit-area present  for each
trophic level--can have a profound  effect on the  magnitude of  the
 «
magnification of perturbations down the food chain from producer to carnivore.
Here  we show  that the  effect of a -1t  change  in the growth rate of
phytoplankton  is greater  on the fish population in  a  food chain with biomass
ratios of 100 : 10 : 1 (phytoplankton  :  zooplankton  :  fish)  than for food
chains  in  which  the  trophic  level ratios are  smaller.    It should be
remembered that we know only that this result pertains  to  the simple  predator-
prey model we have been studying:  the effect of the shape of biomass pyramids
on responses to  stress has yet to be investigated for other types of models.
   Figure 13 presents the response of the  populations in a four-tiered food-
chain model to a -2% perturbation  in the  growth rate  of  the phytoplankton.
Note that,  as in the three-tiered  case (figure 6) the  relative  magnitude  of
changes  in the populations of the various trophic  levels increase as the
organisms get larger.   Another similarity is  that the  lag in response  to
the perturbation is longer for higher trophic  levels.   The four-level model
does, however, appear to be more stable: a -2f perturbation in rx results  in
only a 10$ decrease in the steady-state value of the larger fish population,
while the highest trophic  level in the three-tiered  case  is decreased 30%  in
population.    In the  four-tiered model all four populations  oscillate  in a
damped fashion toward a steady state value.   This  is  the sort of behavior
that one might expect from a real  ecosystem.    It is also gratifying to  note
that the oscillations in the populations  of each predator-prey pair are  out of
phase with each other.   This makes ecological as well as mathematical  sense.
As  the population of larger fish,  for example,  declines, grazing  pressure on
small   fish decreases,  allowing that population to expand.   This  increase in

                                    25

-------
100

P
E
R
c
E 95
N
T
A
0
F

0 90
R
I
G
I
N
A
L 85
P
0
P
80



'• ' V'^x.
J-V \ \
» \ *^»,
\ N ^.
\ N "*— — Icfighic Level Ratios 9:3:1
\ N;
* ^^^^
^ \ Trophic Level Ratios 25:5:1
\ "^ ^^ ^-^.
\ """ ~ — - — 	 .

\
\
\
S
\
\
\
X
\x^
^^^^
*~ 	 	 	
Trophic Level Ratios ldb~:TtTfT~" 	 • 	
rill it
               2000
4000       6000

  TIME IN DAYS
8000
10000
Figure 12 The response  of three different three-tiered  aquatic ecosystems  to
             a -1$ change in the phytoplankton growth  rate.   The  partially
             dashed curves give the response  of the small fish populations
             to the perturbation  for  food chains in which  the initial
             biomass  ratios (per-unit-area biomass of phytoplankton:
             zooplankton: small  fish) are as indicated.   The solid and
             dashed  lines  give  the response  of phytoplankton and
             zooplankton populations for a  food chain with 100:10:1  biomass
             ratios.
                                   26

-------
 110  -
   80
                   5000         10000

                             TIME IN DAYS
                                15000
20000
Figure 13
The response of the populations in a four-tiered aquatic
ecosystem  (measured in biomass  per unit area, initial blomass
ratios:  500 phytoplankton:  100 zooplankton : 10  small  fish: 1
larger fish) to a -2% perturbation in the phytoplankton growth
rate.    The  paths for the responses of  the phytoplankton,
zooplankton,  small fish, and larger fish populations are given
by the upper  solid curve, the dotted curve, and partially
dashed curve,  and  the lower solid curve, respectively.
                                   27

-------
small fish creates favorable conditions for the larger fish, which multiply


until the small fish have been overgrazed.    At this  point  the  population  of



larger fish starts  to decline, the small fish start to increase,  and the cycle



starts again.
 •

   Figures 11 and 15 show the response of the four-tiered ecosystem to a -2%



changes  in r*»  and chart recovery paths  for  cases in which the perturbation  is


removed after 2000  and 1000 days,  respectively.   These two figures illustrate



how important the timing of the removal of a stress can be.    When the stress



is removed after 2000 days there is a pronounced lag  in  the  return path of the



larger fish population.   After 2000 days of recovery that  population is still


less  than  its  pre-perturbation level.   If  the  stress  is removed after  1000



days, the population of larger  fish returns  to  its original  level after  2000



days, and is  actually  10%  above  its  original  level  after  1000 days  of



recovery.   This does not imply, certainly, that it would  be prudent to delay



the clean-up of a polluted aquatic ecosystem in the  hopes that  recovery  will


be faster if one waits longer; it merely illustrates that  the  recovery of a



perturbed ecosystem may not be a simple monotonic function of  the length  of


time over which it  has  been polluted.



   Our mathematical models tend to validate  both the ideal and non-ideal



theoretical hysteresis  models.    Lower trophic levels tend to return to their



original  levels after  a relatively short  recovery time,  and thus show ideal



hysteresis.    For higher trophic  levels (and especially with more severe



stresses) the non-ideal hysteresis model dominates:  larger  organisms  respond



to a stress more slowly and recover more slowly, and frequently  fail to return



to their  initial positions within  a  time-frame relevant  to  policy  decisions.



We should note, however,  that by the nature  of the mathematics used all of the



populations we have modelled will eventually return to  their original  levels,



given a sufficiently long recovery period.




                                    28

                                           \1

-------
  120
P
E
R
C

N
T

0
F
R
I
G
I
N
A
L

P
0
P
  100
90
   60
                                  JL
                                            .L
                    500
                              1000

                          TIME IN DAYS
1500
                                                            2000
 Figure  14    Calculated time paths  for the response and recovery of the
               populations in a four-tiered aquatic ecosystem (measured in
               biomass  per  unit area, initial  biomass  ratios:   500
               phy top lank ton: 100  zooplankton : 10 small fish:  1 larger fish)
               to a -2> perturbation in the phytoplankton growth rate applied
               at time zero and removed after 2000 days.   "Response" paths
               are  indicated  by right-pointing arrows,  and "recovery" paths
               are  marked with left-pointing arrows.   The  paths  for  the
               responses of  the phytoplankton,  zooplankton, small fish, and
               larger  fish populations are given by the upper solid curves,
               the dotted curves,  the  partially  dashed curves, and the lower
               (more highly  arched) solid curves, respectively.   Note that
               the  population of  larger fish fails to return to its original
               position after 2000 days of recovery.
                                    29

-------
p
E
R
C
E
N
0
F
no  -
R
I
G
1
N
A
L

P
0
P
   100
 90  -
    80
                    1000          2000

                              TIME IN DAYS
                                            3000
4000
 Figure  15    Calculated time paths  for the response and recovery of the
              populations in a four-tiered aquatic ecosystem (measured in
              biomass  per  unit area, initial biomass  ratios:   500
              phytoplankton: 100  zooplankton : 10 small  fish: 1 larger fish)
              to a -2J perturbation in the phytoplankton growth rate applied
              at time zero and removed after 4000 days.   "Response" paths
              are  indicated  by right-pointing arrows,  and "recovery"  paths
              are  marked with left-pointing arrows.  The  paths for the
              responses of  the phytoplankton,  zooplankton,small  fish, and
              larger  fish populations are given by the  upper solid  curves,
              the dotted curves,  the  partially  dashed curves, and the  lower
              (more highly  arched) solid curves, respectively.    Note that
              the population of larger fish returns to its original position
              after 2000 days of recovery  and actually  overshoots its
              level by 1000 days  after the  perturbation  is removed.
                                     30

-------
   We expect that the addition of higher trophic levels  including larger,


longer-lived organisms will show the non-ideal  hysteresis model to be more


useful for population changes occuring within a time-frame relevant to policy-


making.
 •





Discussion


   Mathematical  models of ecosystem perturbations are often used  in ecology


(Patten,  1975; O'Neill, 1976)  and aquatic  ecology (O'Melia,  1972;  Bierman et


al,  1980;   Inoue et  al,  1981).   The  drawbacks of such models  are now


sufficiently well understood as to allow  for their restricted use.


   Our mathematically-derived curves for the pollution  and recovery of an


aquatic  ecosystem demonstrate  a hysteresis effect.   These  curves agree


closely  with the  ideal and non-ideal conceptual hysteresis models described


above.   We can use the information in our mathematically-derived curves to


choose which of  the conceptual models is more realistic.


   The non-ideal conceptual  model selected by this process is of great


Interest since it forecasts that the most economically valuable species, such


as commercial and sports  fish,  will not directly and reversibly return to


their original  levels.   This  is due to the  time lags that come about in part


because organisms in higher trophic levels are slower to multiply and in part


because  increases in these  levels must follow  recovery  of their prey


populations.  This type of sustained hysteresis  effect is  apparently inherent


in ecosystems including linked trophic levels.


   Our model differs from many perturbation models (e.g. O'Neill,  1976) in


that we  have assumed that the disturbance caused by pollution is small but


continuous.   This kind  of  small change is to be  expected  from  "modern"


pollution,  where  sophisticated treatment of waste is  mandated and disposal of


the  end  product of  the treatment process cannot be postponed  or diverted.




                                    31

-------
Sewage and industrial-waste effluents from  large cities or companies are



examples  of  such waste streams.   Similarly, it  is  unlikely that  total



restoration of  a  grossly polluted ecosystem would be considered.   Rather, a



small  upgrading  (e.g. through control of point-sources of toxic metals, a



decrease  in  suspended solids,  or a reduction in chlorine  loading) of a



partially restored or partially  damaged system is envisaged,  as opposed to a



massive ecological change.    This sort of approach is typical of pollution-



control strategies currently used in the  U.S.



   There are, however, two potential drawbacks to our simple mathematical



model.    First,  pollution-induced changes in  real  aquatic ecosystems are



unlikely  to be quite as steady and continuous as we have modeled  them.    For



example, many fish scarcely  feed over the winter, and are thus unaffected by



decreases in  algae or zooplankton populations  over that time period.   Second,



our model predicts that small fish will rather quickly be forced nearly to



extinction if larger  (e.g. 25%) continuous depressions  of primary  production



are used.    This is  probably unrealistic  due  to  the  patchy nature of  the



seasonal and spatial distribution of food for  higher-trophic-level organisms.



We expect that some  clarification of these drawbacks will result from  our



future  comparisons of the simple Trophic-Link Model (three trophic and  four



levels) with a five-level version, and the comparison  of both of  these with



real data (yet to be assembled).



   Our deterministic TLM may also be insensitive to other likely ecosystem



stresses that are stochastic in nature.   A cool spring  and summer may,  for



example,  result  in the year's Juvenile fish crop being undersized  at  the  end



of the growth season,  leaving them more  vulnerable to cannibalism  overwinter



(Kipling, 1976).    How would such a random event affect the hysteresis  loops



we have modeled, especially in the recovery phase?  In progressing from a
                                    32

-------
deterministic  to a stochastic modelling approach, the major difference we

would anticipate would  be  that the position of the system would be described

in probabilistic  terms.    For example, with  respect to the -25% perturbation

shown In figure 11, instead of the small  fish population  becoming critically
 *
low  after 3000  days  with a probablity of  one, it  might  do so with a

probability  of 0.9, and have an additional probability of 0.1  of becoming

critical at some other  time.  Ginzburg et al (1982) present a methodology for

obtaining such  extinction  probabilities within the framework of a stochastic

single-species population model.    We intend to consider whether a similar

approach is feasible for a multi-species model with realistic parameters.

   We realize  that the results  of the HTLM are dependent on the form of the

different differential  equations used, the values  chosen  for the  parameters,

the method of solution  of the equations, and the functional components of the

ecosystem that the model describes.   We intend,  in  fact to  examine how

changes in the form and  parameters of HTLM's affect  the results  of such

models.   While no one trophic link model can predict the behavior of a

variety of ecosystems,  or  even  one  specific ecosystem,  with  great certainty,

we hope that advanced forms of the HTLM can be  developed that can,  when

properly  specified and calibrated with field data from  a_ specific ecosystem,

yield meaningful insights into the future behavior of that ecosystem in

response to pollutant stresses.   This does not mean that  we believe any such

model  can  be used to definitively predict that reducing  the annual loading of

compound X by  100 tons per year will result in a 5.5J increase in the number

of game fish.   The  appropriate  use  for a properly calibrated model  would be

as an  aid in making the  type of yes/no choices that regulators often face.

Suppose,  for example,  that a regulator wished to know whether or  not to order

the  clean-up of a specific lake.   If a carefully constructed and calibrated

HTLM indicated that a substantial  fraction of  the  population of  an important


                                    33

-------
game fish would  be  likely to be  lost if clean-up were delayed,  the regulator



might,  after weighing  the  evidence,  decide  to  proceed with  pollution



abatement.    In  such a case it would not matter  if the model predicted a 10{,



60$, 80$, or 100$ reduction in fish: the conclusion drawn by the regulator



would be the same.



   We feel that  the simplicity of the HTLM  framework will make it possible to



easily calibrate models  for  specific situations.   These models could then be



run to yield qualitative information  that,  because  of  the  simplicity of the



models,  can be  traced back  to allow a better understanding of the ecology



behind the result.
   Our initial results suggest that the hysteresis effect may be one reason



why some  valuable fisheries resources (e.g. the Great Lakes, where sports



fisheries have failed to  re-establish themselves following pollution control



efforts)  thave failed to respond to reduction in pollution.    An understanding



of  hysteresis  phenomena  may  also  make  it possible to  predict  (in  an



approximate way)  how  long it will  take  to  see a  recovery of  a fish  resource.



An  equally  important application  of the concept is to use it to gain a



qualitative  feeling for why some components of ecosystems and not others fail



to  show  ideal hysteresis  behavior and consequently become  locally extinct.



Further  calculations using more trophic  levels, different  values for key



parameters, and generation times derived from data on natural  ecosystems, may



show  how useful the hysteresis concept can  be  for economic evaluation of



pollution-control benefits that may be long delayed by ecosystem hysteresis.

-------
References



Bierman,  V.J.,  D.M.  Dolan,  E.F.  Stoermer,  J.E.  Gannon, and  V.E.  Smith




   (1980).   "The Development and Calibration of a Spatially Simplified




   Multi-Class Phytoplankton Model  for Saginaw Bay, Lake Huron".  Great



   Lakes Environmental Planning Study Conference No. 3_.   U.S. Environmental



   Protection  Agency, Grosse Pointe, Michigan.   126 pp.






Christie, W.J. (1976).    "Change  in the Fish Species Composition of the



   Great Lakes".   J., Fish. Res. Bd. Can..  31:  827-851*.






Dillon, P.J.,  and  F.H.  Rigler  (197*0.    "The Phosphorus-Chlorophyll



   Relationship  in Lakes".   Limnol. Oceanogr.  19: 767-773.




Edmondson,  W.T.  (1972).   "The Present Condition  of  Lake Washington".    Verh.



   Int. Ver. Limnol.  18: 284-291.





Edmondson,  W.T.  (1982).    "Daphnia  In Lake  Washington".     Limnol.




   Oceanogr. 27: 272-293.






Ginzburg,  L.R.,  L.B.  Slobodkin,  K.  Johnson,  and  A.G.  Bindman  (1982).




   "Quasiextinction Probabilities as a Measure of Impact  on  Population




   Growth".    Risk Analysis  2: 171-181.






Goldman, C.R., and A.J. Home  (1983).   Limnology.   McGraw-Hill,  M62  pp.



Harte  J.  (1985).    Consider a_ Spherical Cow; A Course  ijn Environmental



   Problem Solving.  William Kaufman Inc., Los Altos, CA.   283 pp.



Hedgepath,  J.W.  (1977).    "Models and  Muddles:  Some Philosophical



   Observations".    Helgol. Wiss. Meeresunters. 30:  92-10M.






Inoue,  Y., S.  Iwai, S.  Ikeda, and T. Kunimatsu (1981).   "Eutrophication of



   Lake Biwa—Nutrient Loadings and Ecological Model".   Verh. Internat.



   Verein. Limnol. 21:2M8-255.






                                   35

-------
Kipling, C.  (1976).    "Year- Class Strengths  of Perch and  Pike in



   Windermere".   Freshwater  Biology Association  Annual  Report  No.  M,  pp.




   68-75.



Malueg, K.W.,  R.M. Brlce, D.W. Schults, and D.P. Larson (1973).   The Shagawa



   Lake Project.   U.S. EPA Report * EPA-R3-73-026,   l»9 pp.






May, R.M.  (1973).   Stability and Complexity iii Model Ecosystems.    Princeton




   University  Press, 235 pp.






Numerical Algorithms Group (1981), "D02EBF -  NAG FORTRAN Library Routine



   Document".    In NAG FORTRAN Library Manual. Mark 11.  v.  1.   Numerical



   Algorithms  Group, Downers  Grove,  Illinois.






O'Melia, C.R.  (1972).   "An Approach  to Modeling of Lakes".   Schweiz. Z._




   Hydrol.   3^:1-33-



O'Neill, R.V.  (1976).    "Ecosystem Persistence and  Heterotrophic



   Regulation".   Ecology 57;121U-1253.






Patten, B.C. (Ed.)  (1975).   Systems  Analysis and Simulation  in Ecology.




   Volume 3.  Academic Press, N.Y., N.Y.   601 pp.






Rigler, F.H. (1976).   Book Review.    Limnol.  Oceanogr.  21;H8l-U83.






Vollenweider,  R.A.  (1969).   The Scientific  Basis  of  Lake  and Stream



   Eutrophication, with  Particular Reference to Phosphorus and  Nitrogen as_




   Eutrophication  Factors.    Technical Report  f  DAS/DSI  68.27,   OECD,  Paris,



   France.



Vollenweider,  R.A., and  J.J. Kerekes  (1980).   OECD Eutrophication  Program,



   Synthesis Report.   OECD,  Paris,  France.



Winberg, G.G.  (1971).   Methods for the Estimation of Production of Aquatic



   Animals.    Academic Press, N.Y.,  N.Y.,  175 pp.






                                   36

-------
APPENDIX:  DETAILS OP MATHEMATICS

-------
                           DETAILS OP MATHEMATICS

ASSUMPTIONS FOR THREE-LEVEL MODEL;

     dX/dt = rxx(1 - X/KX) - B^XY -bxX
     dl/dt = EjyB^yXY - By2TZ - byl
     dZ/dt = EyZByZYZ - b2Z;

X = Phy top lank ton, I = Zooplankton, Z = Small Fish;
Steady-State Populations:  X* = 50, Y* = 10, Z* s  1;
Exy = 0.1, Eyz = 0.1, Kx = 100;
Generation Times:  TX = 3 days, Ty = 20 days, Tz = 360 days

Tx = rx~  » Ty =  (ExyBxyX *~  » Tz  =           "
So...
     rx =
         =  1/TyE^yX* =  (20 x 0.1 x 50)-1  =  10~2,
     Byz =  !/TzEyZY* =  (360 x 0.1 x  10)~1 =  1/360
 At Steady-State:
     rxx*(1 - X*/KX) - BjcyX'Y* -bxx*  =  0
                          - byY*  = 0
      EyzByZY*Z*  - bzZ*  =  0.
 So...
     bx  =  (1/3)(1  -  1/2)  -  (10"2  x  10)  =  1/6 -  0.1  = .0666667
     by  =  (0.1  x TO'2  x  50)  -  (1/360)  = 0.05 -  1/360 = 0.01722
     bz  (0.1  x  1/360 x 10)  = 1/360.
                                     A-l

-------
ASSUMPTIONS FOR FOUR-LEVEL MODEL;

     dX/dt = rxX(1 - X/KX) - B^XY -bxX
     dY/dt = E^BxyXY - ByZYZ - byY
     dZ/dt = EyzBy2YZ - B2fZF - bzZ
     dF/dt = EzfBzfZF - bfF;

X = Phytoplankton, Y = Zooplankton, Z = Small Fish, F = Larger Fish;
Steady-State Populations:  X* = 500, Y* = 100, Z* = 10, F* =  1;
Exy =0.1, Eyz =0.1, Ezf = 0.1, Kx = 1000;
Generation Times:  Tx = 3 days, Ty = 20 days, Tz = 360 days,  Tf  =  1080  days.

Tx = rx'1. Ty =  (ExyBxyxV1, Tz = (EyzBy2YV1, and Tf =  (EzfB2fzV1
So...

     rx  =  (Tx)-1  =  (3)~1  =  1/3,
     Bxy =  1/TyExyX* = (20 x 0.1 x 500)-1 =  10~3,
     Byz =  1/T2EyZY* = (360 x 0.1 x 100)~1 =  1/3600, and
     B2f =  1/TfEzfZ* = (1080 x 0.1 x  10)~1 =  1/1080.

At Steady-State:

     rxX*(1  - X-/KX) - BxyX*Y* -bxX*  =  0
     ExyBxyxV  - ByzY*Z* - byY* = 0

     SyzByz**2*  ' Bzfz*F* ' bzz* = °» and
     EzfBzfZ*F*  - bfF* =  0.
So...
     bx  = (1/3M1 - 1/2)  -  (10"3 x  100) =  1/6 -  0.1  =  .0666667
     by  = (0.1 x 10~3 x  500)  -  (1/3600  x  10)  = 0.05  -  1/360  = O.OH722
     bz  (0.1 x  1/3600 x  100)  -  (1/1080) =  1/360  -  1/1080  = 1/5^0,  and
     bf  (0.1 x  1/1080 x  10)  =  1/1080.

                                    A-2

-------
            LISTING OF COMPUTER PROGRAM USED TO CALCULATE  TIME PATHS FOR

                        THREE-LEVEL AQUATIC BCOSTSTB4 MODEL
 c       This program, which incorporates the NAG subroutine do2ebf, can
 c       be used to solve three coupled differential equations.
 c        ..scalars in common
         implicit double precision (a-h.o-z)
         double precision H. xend
         integer I
 c
 c        ..local scalars..
         double precision tol, x
         integer Ifail. JR. 1W. mped, nout
 c        ..local arrays..
         double precision W(3.2l). Y(3)
 c        ..subroutine references..
 c       d02ebf
 c
         external fen. out. pederv
         common xend, H, ]
         open(8. file='output')
 c       opens file, named "output", in which results are to be placed
         data nout /6/
         write (nout.99996)
         write (8.99996)
         write (nout.99994)
         write (8.99994)
         N = 3
         IW=21
         MPED = 0
         1R = 2
         tol = 10.0dO«»(-5)
         write  (nout.99999) tol
         write  (nout.99998)
         write  (8.99999) tol
         write  (8.99998)
         x = 0
         zend = 1.0d4
c        Program is now set to calculate a "response" path.  To calculate a
c        "return" path one would substitute post-perturbation values for
c        y(l-3) below
         y(l) = SO.OdO
         y(2) = lO.OdO
        y(3) = l.OdO
         H = (xend-x)/50
c        Prints out solution at 49 evenly spaced points between x(0) and xend
        1 = 49
        Ifail = 1
        call D02EBF(x. xend. N. y. tol. IR. fen. mped, pederv,
        • out. W. IW. Ifail)
        write (nout.99997) Ifail
        write (8.99997) Ifail


                                         A-3

-------
       subroutine pederv(x. y, PW) •
 c      ..scalar arguments..
       double precision z
 c      ..array arguments..
       double precision PW(3.3). y(3)
 c
       PW(l.l) = -1.00dO'2.0dO"(1.0dO/(3.0dO«100.0dO))«y(l) +
       +  + 1.00dO'(1.0dO/3.0dO)-0.0666666666666667dO
       +  -  (1.0dO/100.0dO)"y(2)
       PW(1.2) = (I.0d0/100.0d0)«y(l)
       PW(1.3) = O.OdO
       PW(2.1) = (1.0dO/100.0dl)»y(2)
       PW(2.2) = -(I.0d0/36.0dl)*y(3)- (4.72222222222d-2) +
       +    (1.0dO/100.0dl)»y(l)
       PW(2.3) = -(1.0dO/36.0dl)*y(2)
       PW(3.1) = O.OdO
       PW(3.2) = (I.0d0/36.0d2)»y(3)
       PW(3.3) = (I.0d0/36.0d2)*y(2) - 1.0000dO»(l.OdO/3.8d2)
       return
       end
       subroutine out(x. y)
c       ..scalar arguments..
       double precision x. u
c       ..array arguments..
       double precision y(3)
       double precision z(3)
c      u allows time to be counted "backwards" (for return paths), while z(3)
c      is a set of variables that allow the populations, y(t). to be normalized
c      with respect to one another.  The equations for z(l-3) below express
c      each y(t) as a percentage of the initial population in that trophic level
c
c       ..scalars in common..
       double precision H, xend
       integer I
c
c       ..local scalars..
       integer J, nout
c
       common xend. H. I
       data nout /6/
       z(l) =  y(l)/0.5dO
       z(2) =  y(2)*10.0dO
       z(3) =  y(3)M.Od2
       u = 1.0d4 - x
       write (nout.99999) x. (z(J).J=l,3)
       write (8.99999) x. (z(J).J=1.3)
       x = xend - dble(I)*H
       1 = 1-1
       return
99999  format (1H , FB.2. 3E13.5)
      end
                                         A-4

-------
            If (toUt.o) write (nout.99995)
            If (tol.lt.o) write (8,99995)
         20 continue
            mped = 1
      c      mped = 1 indicates that routine is using supplied J accsi^ni^r- {in PEDERV)
      c      rather than calculating it internally (which happens wrrssrrn mped = 0)
            write (nout,99993)
            write (8.99993)
            tol = 10.0dO**(-5)
            write (nout.99999) tol
            write (8,99999) tol
            write (8,99998)
            write (nout.99998)
            x = 0
            xend = 1.0d4
            y(l) = SO.OdO
            y(2) = lO.OOdO
            y(3) s l.OdO
            H = (xend-x)/50
            1 = 49
            Ifail = 1
            call D02EBF(x. xend. N. y. tol, IR, fen, mped. pederv.
           • out. W. IW, Ifail)
            write (nout.99997) Ifail
            If (tol.lt.o) write (nout.99995)
            write (8.99997) Ifail
            If (toLlt.o) write (8.99995)
         40 continue
            stop
      99999 format (22hOCALCULATION WITH TOL=.  e8.1)
      99998 format (40b T AND SOLUTION AT EQUALLY SPACED POINTST
      99997 format (8h Ifail= II)
      99996 format (4(lx/). 31h D02EBF EXAMPLE PROGRAM RESULT
      99995 format (24h RANGE TOO SHORT FOR TOL)
      99994 format (32hOCALCULATING JACOBIAN INTERNALLY)
      99993 format OlhoCALCULATING JACOBIAN BY PEDERV)
            end
            subroutine fcn(T. y. F)
     %       ..scalar arguments-
           double precision T
r             ..array arguments..
           double precision F(3). y(3)
I
             .  j = 1.00dO*(1.0dO/3.0dO)*y(l)*(l.OdO-(y(l)/100.0dC   -
           +  (I.0d0/100.0d0)*y(l)'y(2)
           + - 0.066666666666667dO*y(l)
            F(2) = (l.OdO/100.0dl)*y(D*y(2) - ((l.OdO/36.0dl)«y(2)T
           + (4.72222222222d-2)»y(2)
            F(3) = (I.0d0/36.0d2)»y(2)*y(3) - 1.00dO«(l.OdO/3.6d2)J
            Program is now set at steady state.  To model a
            in the phytoplakton growth rate, replace "l.OOdO" in the ?~
            for F(l) (and also in the expression for PW(l.l). below)
     c      with, for example, "0.98dO" (for a 2% decrease)
           (return
           end
     I
                                             A-5

-------
          LISTING OP COMPUTER PROGRAM OSKD  TO CALCULATE TIMB PATHS FOR

                       POUR-LEVEL AQUATIC  ECOSYSTEM MODEL

 c      ..scalars in common
       implicit double precision (a-h.o-z)
       double precision H, xend
       integer I
 c
 c      ..local scalars..
       double precision tol.  x
       integer Ifail. JR, IW, mped, nout
 c      ..local arrays..
       double precision W(4.22). Y(4)
 c      ..subroutine references..
 c     d02ebf
 c
       external fen, out. pederv
       common xend. H. I
       open(8. flle='output')
 c     Places the output of this program into a file named "output"
       data nout /6/
       write (nout.99996)
       write (8.99996)
       write (nout.99994)
       write (8.99994)
       N = 4
       IW = 22
       MPED = 0
       IR = 2
       tol = 10.0dO*'(-5)
       write (nout.99999) tol
       write (nout.99998)
       write (8.99999) tol
       write (8.99998)
       x = 0
 c     Program is now set to calculate time paths starting with steady-state
 c     conditions.  To calculate "return" paths, replace the values of
 c     y(l-3) below with post-perturbation values
       xend = 2.0d4
       y(l) = 500.0dO
       y(2) = lOO.OdO
       y(3) = lO.OdO
       y(4) = l.OdO
       H = (xend-x)/50
       1 = 49
       Ifail =  1
       call D02EBF(x. xend. N, y. tol. IR. fen. mped. pederv,
      • out. W. IW. Ifail)
       write (nout.99997) Ifail
       write (8,99997) Ifail
       If (tol.lt.o) write (nout.99995)
       If (tol.lt.o) write (8,99995)
    20 continue
c      This section, which is optional, calculates time points based on values
c      of the Jacobian matrix of the system supplied in "PEDERV". below
       mped = 1
       write (nout.99993)
       write (8.99993)                     A_6

-------
      tol = 10.0dO»*(-5)
      write (nout.99999) tol
      write (8.99999) tol
      write (8.99998)
      write (nout.99998)
      x = 0
      xend = 2.0d4
      y(l) = SOO.OdO
      y(2) = lOO.OdO
      y(3) = lO.OdO
      y(4) = l.OdO
      H = (xend-x)/50
      1 = 49
      Ifail = 1
      call D02EBF(x, xend. N. y. tol. IR. fen. mped. pederv.
      • out. W. IW. Ifail)
      write (nout.99997) Ifail
      If (tol.lt.o) write (nout.99995)
      write (8.99997) Ifail
      If (toUt.o) write (8.99995)
   40 continue
      stop
99999 format (22hCALCULATION WITH TOL=. eB.l)
99998 format (40h T AND SOLUTION AT EQUALLY SPACED POINTS)
99997 format (8h Ifail= II)
99996 format (4(lx/), 31h D02EBF EXAMPLE PROGRAM RESULTS/lx)
99995 format (24h RANGE TOO SHORT FOR TOL)
99994 format (32hCALCULATING JACOBIAN INTERNALLY)
99993 format (31hCALCULATING JACOBIAN BY PEDERV)
      end
      subroutine fcn(T. y. F)
c      ..scalar arguments..
      double precision T
c      ..array arguments..
      double precision F(4). y(4)
c
c     To calculate response to a perturbation in the phytoplankton growth rate,
c     replace "l.OOdO" in F(l). and PW(1,1) below with, for example "0.98dO"
c     (for a -2% perturbation
      F(l) = 1.00dO*(1.0dO/3.0dO)»y(l)*(1.0dO-(y(l)/100.0dl)) -
      +   (1.0dO/100.0dl)*y(l)*y(2)
      -«• -0.066666866666667dO»y(l)
      F(2) = (1.0dO/100.0d2)*y(l)*y(2) - ((I.0d0/36.0d2)»y(2)'y(3)) -
      + (4.72222222222d-2)*y(2)
      F(3) = (1.0dO/36.0d3)*y(2)-y(3) - ((1.0dO/1080.0dO)»y(3)'y(4)) -
      +   1.00dO«(1.0dO/5.4d2)-y(3)
      F(4) = (1.0dO/1080.0dl)»y(3)»y(4)  - ((l.OdO/1080.0dO)*y(4))
      return
      end
                                       A-7

-------
       subroutine pederv(x, y. PW)
c       ..scalar arguments..
       double precision z
c       ..array arguments..
       double precision PW(4,4), y(4)
c                                 '
       PW(l.l) = -1.00dO«2.0dO*(1.0dO/(3.0dO*100.1dO))*y(l) +
      + + 1.00dO«(l.OdO/3.0dO)-0.0866686666668887dO
      + - (I.0d0/100.0dl)»y(2)
       PW(1,2) = (1.0dO/100.0dl)»y(0
       PW(1,3) = O.OdO
       PW(1,4) = O.OdO
       PW(2,1) = (1.0dO/100.0d2)»y(2)
       PW(2.2) = -(1.0dO/36.0d2)«y(3) - (4.72222222222d-2) +
      +   (1.0dO/100.0d2)»y(l)
       PW(2,3) = -(1.0dO/36.0d2)"y(2)
       PW(2,4) = O.OdO
       PW(3,1) = O.OdO
       PW(3,2) = (1.0dO/36.0d3)»y(3)
       PW(3,3) = (I.0d0/36.0d3)*y(2) - 1.00dO*(1.0dO/5.4d2) -
      +   (1.0dO/1080.0dO)»y(4)
       PW(3,4) = (1.0dO/1080.0dO)»y(3)
       PW(4.1) = O.OdO
       PW(4.2) = O.OdO
       PW(4.3) = (I.0d0/1080.0dl)*y(4)
       PW(4.4) = (1.0dO/1080.0dl)'y(3) - (I.0d0/1080.0d0)
       return
       end
       subroutine out(x, y)
c       ..scalar arguments..
       double precision x,  u
c       ..array arguments..
       double precision y(4)
       double precision z(4)
c      "u" allows time to be counted "backwards" for return time paths; z(l-4)
c      is a set of variables that allow the time points for y(l-4) to be
c      expressed as percentages of the initial populations in each trophic
c      level
c
c       ..scalars in common..
       double precision H.  xend
       integer I
c
c       ..local scalars..
      integer J. nout
c
      common xend. H. I
      data nout /8/
      z(l) = y(l)/0.5dl
      z(2) = y(2)
      z(3) = y(3)*1.0dl
      z(4) = y(4)»1.0d2
      u = 2.0d3 - x
      write (nout,99999) u, (z(J).J=1.4)
      write (8.99999) u. (z(J).J=1.4)
      x = xend - dble(I)*H
      1 = 1-1
      return
99999 format (1H . F8.2. 4E13.5)
       end

                                           A-3

-------
                                                                            r-,
                                CHAPTER ^






                  Ecotoxicology and Benefit-Cost Analysis:




                       The Role of Error Propagation
Introduction
   An understandable desire exists on the part of policy makers to devise a



set of procedures, an analytical approach, that can be used to guide policy.



Such an approach  would  obviate the need  for  trusting to historical practice,



or to the intuition of wise  but inevitably fallible  and probably biased



individuals,  or  to  the awkward and time-consuming process of making every



decision  by  plebiscite.    It  would "rationalize"  policy making and,  if the



procedure were  appropriately  chosen, optimize the well-being of the affected



sector of the public.   Pollution abatement policy is  a prime example, for



it is here that a vigorous effort is underway to promote  benefit-cost analysis



as the appropriate analytical approach  for determining proper emission  levels



(see U.S. Executive Order  12291).



   Despite the  advantages in efficiency  of decision making,  and  possibly in



enhancement of societal  welfare,  that may accrue to a society that employs the



benefit-cost approach  to set pollution emission  levels, there  are major



pitfalls  lurking that need to be  identified and discussed.    These pitfalls



fall into two categories:  limitations in  the ability of ecologists to describe



precisely the  ecological consequences of  pollutant  emission rates,  and



limitations  in the ability of economists to describe precisely the economic



consequences of ecological changes.



   Quite  generally,  the economic and ecological analyses that are required to



characterize and quantify  costs and benefits of  particular pollutant abatement



strategies consist  of a  sequence of  steps.    Table 1 shows what  a typical



sequence of steps would  have to  look like for a believable benefit-cost






                                    1

-------
 Change in a polluting activity
 (e.g., placement of scrubbers
 in power plants)
    i.
(combustion science)
I  Change in emission levelsI
  (e.g. reduction in SOg output)    |
    2.
(atmospheric  sciences)
 Change in primary stress on
 ecosystem (e.g., increase in pH
 of precipitation at a particular
 watershed)
    3
 (biogeochemistry)
Change in secondary stresses  (which  I
act directly on biological  populations
and processes)  (e.g.,  increase  in  pHl
of surface waters and  soils)         I
    4    I
(biological toxicology)
 Direct biological effects of changes
 in secondary  stresses  (e.g.,increase
 in populations of acid-sensitive
 plankton)
      5.1
Direct market value of
changed use patterns and
of indirect benefits (e.g.,
value of user-day fees and
additional water supply);
value of other benefits
(e.g., feelings of civic
accomplishment, spiritual
satisfaction)
 (ecology)
 Indirect ecological  changes
 stimulated by the direct  biological
 effects (e.g.,  improvement in
 fish productivity)
                                         (economics  and  the
                                          political  process)
     6.
             (environmental sciences,
              sociology, ...)
         Change in pattern of direct use of ecosystem
         (e.g., fishermen flock to site)

         Change in indirect ecological benefits to
         society  (e.g., hydrologic integrity of
         watershed is enhanced, leading to reduction
         in fluctuations of water supplies to people)
                                                                    7.
                Table 1.  The stages of ecosystem  impact  assessment

-------
analysis, with the example of acid rain used to provide specificity.   The



information that must be used to quantify any given step in the  sequence must



come from analysis at the preceding stage.    Thus the possibility exists that



error may propagate through the sequence to  the point where the final output—



for  example,  the economic  benefit  of a particular level  of pollution



abatement—is so uncertain as to  be  of little or no use in a  benefit-cost



analysis  or related procedure.



   Whether or not this  occurs will depend  in  part  on the degree to which



ecologists and other environmental  scientists can characterize the uncertainty



in a manner that  can be used by  economists.    To take a  simple example,



consider  the statement that the decrease in fish mortality  following pollution



abatement in a particular lake is  uncertain.   This  statement may mean that



the decrease in mortality cannot be predicted accurately but that the  odds of



any specified degree of decrease in mortality are known (from some combination



of measurement  and modeling).    Or   it may mean that  only the  range of



uncertainty is known but that the  probabilities of any particular value of



mortality within that range are not known.   In the former case, economists



may be able  to estimate an expected value of benefit of any particular degree



of abatement (using methods such as those described elsewhere in this report),



whereas in the latter case the opportunity to characterize the  benefit of any



particular degree of abatement is considerably more limited.



   In the remainder of this chapter we discuss in a systematic and general



manner the subject of error propagation in environmental  impact assessment,



with an emphasis on impacts involving ecosystems.   We deduce some general



results  about error propagation that are independant of the  method of



analysis.   One  key  result is  that error tends  to "biomagnify" in ecological



food chains,  so that a  small degree  of uncertainty about the effect of a



pollutant on  the lowest trophic level is likely to translate  into  much more

-------
substantial uncertainty  about  the effects on higher trophic levels,  in  which



we are often more interested.    We also explore the origin of some of the



most refractory  types  of error in impact assessment.    To  relate  the  analysis



to the specific  concerns of practitioners of economic evaluation  we also show



how the relevant issue is not merely  one of  the magnitude of the range of



uncertainty but also of the type of uncertainty; this  is because economic



analysis,  which  must begin where  ecological analysis leaves off, can cope with



some kinds of uncertainties better than  others.   Of particular concern in the



context of benefit-cost  analysis  is the degree to which sources of ecological



uncertainties can be characterized in ways  that will be of  use to economists.



The overall  dimensions and a  few  critical  elements of  this  problem are



discussed here,  but it  will be  shown that considerable  work on the part of



ecologists will  be necessary to bridge  the  gap between what is now  known and



what needs to be known to provide a plausible underpinning for the successful



application of benefit-cost  methods of decision-making.








Uncertainty iii Impact Assessment; an  Example



   Examples of error propagation in  environmental science abound.    Consider



the acid rain example from Table  1.   Analysts have attempted to establish the



existence  and valuse  of a  threshold  level of precipitation pH,  below  which



lakes would become  acidic and above which the natural restorative capacity of



lakes and  surrounding  soils  would afford protection.    The existence of such a



threshold would make the task  of setting  standards  easier because such a



threshold  would  provide  a natural level to aim for—tightening  the standard



beyond the threshold would lead  to diminishing returns.



   However, uncertainties in impact  assessment render  the threshold  notion a



highly dubious  one in  this context.   It  is likely,  in fact, that  one's

-------
perception  of  the  location  of  the  threshold  for a  particular class of lakes



depends on how long one has been observing those lakes under  various levels of



exposire; whereas precipitation with a pH of,  say,  1.5 might acidify the lakes



in 10 years, precipitation with a higher pH of, say, 4.9 might acidify the



lakes in 30 years, a. period longer  than anyone has had the opportunity to



observe.    Thus the threshold concept  is time-dependent and  intrinsic



uncertainty  characterizes  its evaluation



   The threshold value for one class of lakes might not be of much use for



others.   For  example, in eastern North America it has been pointed out that



over several decades, the  period over which observations have been made, lakes



receiving  precipitation with  a pH  of less than  about  U.7  have had their



chemistry altered  by  the  precipitation.   Even if  we  accept this relatively



short time-frame  for  that particular group of  lakes,   there is  still



uncertainty as  to  the  value  of this  "threshold" in other areas.   In the



mountains of the western  United States, for  example, the susceptibility of



lakes to acidification  appears  to be greater than in  watersheds of the



northeastern  U.S.  (Roth  et al,   1985).   A more  complete discussion of



uncertainties  plaguing  the  use of  the threshold concept  in ecotoxicology is



found in Cairns and Harte  (1985).



   Even if  we  had confidence in the location of  a pH threshold, we would still



not know exactly  what the effect on  precipitation  pH would  be  for any



specified emissions  reduction plan.   Here the uncertainty stems from the



complexity  of  the source-receptor relation.



   The uncertainty  in deducing the  effect of  a  particular  level of emissions



reduction on precipitation pH must  be combined with the further uncertainty in



deducing the  effect of a reduction  in precipitation  pH on surface water



acidity.    By  combining these  two  uncertainties,  the  overall  uncertainty in



steps 2  to  U of Table 1 can be  determined.    At the other  stages in the impact

-------
assessment further  opportunity for error arises.   The  combined error is




almost invariably sufficiently large to  make it difficult to obtain a precise




characterization of the ecological benefits from a particular emissions-




reduction  plan.




   The  fact  that one  cannot  precisely  characterize the  benefits  of a




pollution-abatement policy should not he taken to mean that the policy is



unwarranted.   Even  though an economic analysis might not  produce a reliable




cost-benefit ratio, it can lead  to a range of uncertatinty in that ratio,



which can  then  be  evaluated  through the political  process to  determine what




policy  action  is warranted.    The first  step,  however,  must be to have a




systematic approach  to the analysis of uncertainty;  this  is discussed in the




following  section.








^ Framework for Analysis




   The sequence of steps, in an environmental impact assessment as shown on the



left hand  side  of Table  1  provides a  convenient  framework for  analysing the




propagation of  error in  such  assessments.    Generally,  the relation between




the ith and the i+1st stage in the sequence is  likely to look  like one of the




three graphs shown in figure  1.   In each  of the graphs, the horizontal axis




represents the  variable describing  the  i^h stage  and  the vertical  axis




represents the  subsequent one down the  chain.   The first of these three



graphs illustrates a linear relation, in which  the response, or output, at the




subsequent stage is proportional to the  input from the one before, as, for




example, if the loss of organisms is proportional to the  concentration of a



pollutant.   The second one  illustrates a threshold  process, in which an




output is  only weakly dependent on an input for small values of the input, but




when the input exceeds a critical  value, then  the output rises sharply.   The

-------
           a.
b.
                                                                   Xi
                                c.
                                           Xi
                           Figure  1

Illustration of a linear (a), a threshold (b), and a saturation (c) process
relating variables describing successive  stages in the assessment chain.

-------
third graph in Figure  1  illustrates  a  saturation process,  in which an output

ceases 'to be strongly dependent on input once the input exceeds a critical

value.

   These three basic  types  of relations between  sequential stages in the

impact chain  can  be modified or combined  to describe, generically,  most

real processes.    For example,  the graphs  can be turned  upside  down  to

describe  processes in which an output is a decreasing function of input.    Or

graphs  1-b and 1-c can be combined to describe a process  with a threshold at a

relatively low value of the  input and a saturation effect at a higher  one.

   If knowledge of the functional relation between two  sequential stages in

the chain were complete, and the input data were  known with perfect precision

and accuracy* then a graph  of the function describing the relation might,

indeed,  look something  like  one of the  plots  in  Figure  1,   But, in  reality,

there is always uncertainty  in both knowledge of functional relations and in

the data  needed to substitute into those functions.   These uncertainties  will

propagate  down the impact chain, sometimes leading to a surprisingly  high

level of uncertainty at the  end.

   Two types of uncertainty were alluded to  above.   one  results from poor

knowledge of  the dynamics  of the  processes--!.e.  uncertainty  in  our

understanding  of  the  form of the relation between variables—and one  results

from incertain numerical values for  data.   For example, suppose that we are

interested in  estimating the uncertainty in our knowledge of the lessening of

damage to plankton populations due to an expected  decline in the  rate  of input

of a pollutant to a lake.    Because it is difficult  to  predict with  high
 "Precision" refers to the detail  with which a number is expressed—the number
of significant figures.   "Accuracy" refers to how close the number is to the
true, or  real,  value.   Thus  if I state my  height is 3-47258 meters, I am
being precise  but inaccurate.   Oftentimes authors will substitute precision
for accuracy, providing more significant figures than the data deserve and
giving the illusion that they are  highly accurate.

-------
accuracy how the concentration of a pollutant  in a lake will respond to a



change in the  input  rate,  there will  be  uncertainty in our knowledge of what



the concentration of pollutant  in  the  lakewater will be.   On top of that we



will have,  at best, only partial knowledge of how the plankton population will



respond to any precisely  stated change in the pollutant concentration.    In



other words, even  with  perfectly accurate data describing the pollutant, our



knowledge  of  the  functional  form  of the  relation  between  pollutant



concentration and plankton survivability is uncertain.



   Because  of  the  uncertainty  in our knowledge of functional relations,  the



graphs shown in Figure 1 must be modified  as in Figure 2.    Furthermore,



because  the  input data  (the  horizontal axis  variable) are likely  to be



uncertain,  the  output (the vertical  axis variable) is  also  going  to have an



uncertainty that reflects  the fuzziness of the input  data.    At  each stage in



the chain, the uncertainty may be  amplified or damped  as uncertainty in the



output from one stage becomes uncertainty in  the input to the next.   Figure 3



provides a generic  illustration  of how the error will propagate down the



chain.    The range of uncertainty is shown  to broaden in  the  figure, a result



of the width and steepness of the  functional  forms assumed.    If probability



distributions  characterizing  the likelihood of the parameters  taking on



particular values within the  range of  uncertainty are known, then a more




sophisticated analysis  can be  carried  out; shown here is the simpler case in



which only  the  propagation of the range of uncertainty is described.



   A useful analysis of the consequences for policy makers of this sort of



error propagation is given in Reckhow  (1984).  In the  following section,  we



discuss some general results about uncertainty  that  can be deduced from the



above considerations.

-------
                        xi
           xi
             a.
b.
                                    c.
                               Figure  2
Examples of error bands in the curves shown in Figure 1,
                              10

-------
              Ax,
                                            Figure 3
Illustration of the propagation of error along the assessment chain,
in Xj is "passed along" to Xi+1 in the manner shown.
In each graph, the uncertainty

-------
General Results;  The  "Fallacy of the Mean" and "Error Biomagnification"



   Quantities such as  fish productivity or water clarity,  indeed any parameter



to which  a numerical  range  can be ascribed, can be characterized by a mean



value and a  range of uncertainty about that mean.   Because it is much simpler



to focus  on a mean value, which  is a single number, rather than on the range



of uncertainty, which is at the very  least a range of numbers (often with a



complicated  interpretation attached explaining what  that  range  really refers



to) it is not uncommon for analysts to be asked questions such as "if I take



the mean  value of the pollutant concentration and substitute  that into the



formula relating concentration to plankton survivability,  then what mean value



will  I obtain for plankton  survivability?"   This question  reflects a



fundamental  confusion:  a function  evaluated  at  the mean  value  of its



independent variable is generally not equal to  the mean value of the function.



Indeed,   as shown below,  considerable error can  result if mean values are



estimated by commiting this "fallacy of the mean".



   How will the general shape of the  graph  (as is Figure 1) of the relation



between  two successive stages in impact assessment influence the error



committed by assuming  that a function of the mean equals the mean of the



function?   Figure *l  illustrates the  answer to this question.   In this



figure,  the parameter,  a, has an equal probability of lying anywhere in the



range from B to C and its mean is midway between  at E.   At the upper end of



this range,  x(a) takes on the value D while  at the lower end it takes on the



value A.   As the figure shows, if  the relation between an independent



variable, a, and a  dependent variable,  x, is linear,  then despite uncertainty



in our knowledge of a, the  mean value of x, denoted by x,  is  equal  to x(a)



evaluated at  g,  the  mean value  of a.   In equation form, X =  x(a).   For  the



case of a threshold-type relation, this figure  shows why X > x(a), while  for a



saturation  process, X <  x(a).





                                   12

-------
X(a)
X(a)
                                                               B     E
     a.    IF  BE=EC, THEN AB=CD
       b.    IF BE=EC,  THEN  DOBA
                           c.   IF BE=EC,  THEN AB>CD

                                   Figure  4

     The relation between the mean value of X  and the value of X evaluated  at  the
     mean value of  the parameter, a, upon which  it  depends, is shown for  the
     three  cases of a linear (a),  upward curving (b), and downward curving (c)
     relation  between X and  a.

                                        13

-------
   This  can be very important  in practice; for  relations characterized by very
steeply  curved functions, the  use of the mean  value of the  independent
variable for evaluating the mean value of the dependent one can lead to a
gross under- or over-estimation, depending on the type of curvature in the
functional relation.   To illustrate this, we present the following example.
   The attenuation of light with depth in a relatively transparent lake obeys
a simple formula: I(d) = IQ exp(-vd), where I(d) is the intensity at depth d,
Io is the intensity of  light at the surface, and  v  is  a constant
characterizing the transparency of the water.   The more opaque the water, the
larger  the value of  v  .   Primary productivity of aquatic  plants at any
particular depth will  be roughly proportional  to the value of  I at that depth,
although it also  depends, of course,  on concentrations of essential nutrients
such as  nitrate and phosphate.   Suppose siltation results in a large value of
v .   We will assume that the  mean  value of v is  0.3/meter and that the range
of uncertainty is +_ 0.02/meter.    We will interpret this range to mean (for
the sake of  simplicity)  that the actual value of v is equally likely to lie
anywhere in the range from 0.28 to 0.32/meter.   Suppose erosion control is
expected to  reduce  the  value of v  to 0.17 +. 0.09,  with the range  of
uncertainty  increased  because  it  is  not known how  effective the  control
program will  be.   At a depth of, say,  20 meters, the mean value of I  prior to
the erosion control that would be calculated (incorrectly) by  substituting  the
mean  value of v  into the formula for I(d)  is  Io exp(-6.0) or 0.0025  IO'
After  the   control   is   implemented,  the   similarly  incorrect  value is
Io exp(-3.M)  = 0.033IO»  an increase of I by a  factor of about 12.   However,
if the actual mean value of I is  calculated properly, not by substituting into
exp(- vd) the  mean value of v but  rather  averaging  over the  range of
uncertainty  in  v ,  then we find that erosion control results, on  the average,
in twice as great an increase in mean  light intensity  at  20 meters.    Leaving

-------
aside subtleties such as whether plants respond to the average light intensity



they  receive  or  to  some more  complicated  value  that  depends  on  the



fluctuations,  there  is  clearly a  large potential  for error  in naively



estimating mean values by being oblivious to the uncertainties.



   We emphasize that the propagation  of error by  this means can result either



from a situation where  one knows what the uncertainties are but uses  the



incorrect formula relating mean values, or from a situation  where one simply



under- or overestimates the magnitudes of the uncertainties but uses a correct



averaging procedure for estimating mean values.



   In the modular approach to error propagation discussed in the previous



section, there is an  opportunity  for  errors  of  this  type  to either  be



reinforced or  to  cancel.    If a  sequence of  relations between  the  variables



describing the successive stages in the impact chain are all of, say,  the



threshold  type, or  more  generally, of any  similar curvature,  then the error



propagation that results from ignorance of  the  true range of uncertainty will



be reinforcing, leading to greater and greater error as one moves along  the



chain.   In contrast,  if curves  of types  1.b and 1.c from Figure 1  are equally



represented in the chain, then the tendency will be for  the errors of that



type to cancel.



   Next, we  turn  to the  topic of "error biomagnification".    Error,  like many



a toxic substance,  will  frequently increase as one probes higher up the food



chain  (not  to be  confused with the  impact assessment  chain  in Fig.  1),



although the mechanism that accounts for error biomagnification is quite



different  from  that for  toxic substance biomagnification.    To  see how error



biomagnification arises,  consider the following relatively simple model for a



food chain.   Figure 5  illustrates the model, showing the inflows and outflows



of biomass from each  link in the chain.     The links can be thought of as
                                   15

-------
                                              aN XN
                                                            6N-1,N XN-1 XN
                             ]   6N-1,N XN-1 XN
        al  Xl
                                e34 x3 x4
                                 23
                                 12
                                              a2 X2 + Y2 X2
                            Figure 5

A trophic chain and the rates of biomass input and output from each link in
the chain as described by a simple Lotka-Volterra model.
                                 16

-------
species (for example, grass, which is eaten by rabbits, which are eaten by


lynx,  etc.) or as functional groupings of  species (for example,  primary


producers, herbivores, first carnivores,  . . . and on up to top carnivores).


In equation form,  the model reads as follows:



                 dX1

                 ---  = 01X1 - Y1X12 - 612X1X2
                 dt


                 dX2

                 ---  = E12&12X1X2 . a2X2 _  Y2X22 - ^23X2X3
                 dt
                                               -  3^X3X4
                 dt
                 "*
                 dt
   In these  equations,  the X^  are the biomasses  of the components;  the


coefficients gji are rate constants describing the predation of species j


upon species  i;  the coefficients  E^j describe the efficiency of incorporation


of prey biomass by the predator;  and the coefficients at and yi are srowth and


death  rates  for the individual species.    The presence of the y^ terms


represents a negative feedback mechanism induced by the finite carrying


capacity of any realistic environment.   They result in steady-state solutions


that are stable  against perturbations such  as  the removal  of  some percentage


of the biomass of the system.    Indeed, the only solution to  these equations


is one in which  all the  Xi approach  time-independent  values.   Although real


populations are not  found  in steady-state  (that is, the numbers of


individuals  in real populations  generally exibit both cyclic  and  random time


dependence),   models with  steady-state  solutions  are  often  used to study the
                                   17

-------
time-averaged behavior of such populations.    Although  simple models of this


sort are generally unreliable for making detailed  predictions of the values of


the variables, Xi(t)>  they are useful  for exploring the qualitative features


of ecosystems.


   Suppose  that  the growth rate of the  primary producers is affected by a


pollutant,  but that there is  some uncertainty  about  the magnitude of the


effect.    In other  words,  suppose that the value  of a1 ig known only to  be in


the range between  $1  + a  and a-) -a  where $1 *s fche mean value and o is a


measure of the uncertainty in the mean.    How will the uncertainty in  affect


the uncertainty in  the steady-state values of the individual  variables,  Xj.?


A simple two-level model illustrates  the general idea:
                      --- = aiX-| - Y1X-T - 612X1X2
                      dt
                      dX2

                      --- = E12$12X1X2 - a2X2  -
                      dt
For this case the  steady-state solutions for the X^ are:
                                ---------------   and

                                E-I2&122 + Y1Y2
A measure of the relative uncertainty in the Xi caused  by  the uncertainty  in


»i is (a/XiXSXi/Sotj).   Thus the ratio of the relative uncertainty in X-|  to


that in X2»  which  we  denote by Ri2» *3
                                 (a/X2)(3X2/3a1)


This can be shown to equal (Y2X2)/(a2 + Y2X25' wnich is  less than unity-
                                    18

-------
 other words, the relative  error in X2  induced by the uncertainty in 
-------
  110  -
   50
                2000
4000       6000

  TIME IN DAYS
8000
10000
Figure 6a

The  response  of  the  populations  in a  three-tiered  aquatic
ecosystem (measured in biomass per unit area, Initial  blomass
ratios:  50  phytoplankton:  10  zooplankton : 1 small fish) to -1f,
-2%, and -3f changes in the phytoplankton growth rate.  Solid,
dotted, and  (partially)  dashed  lines  give  the paths for
phytoplankton, zooplankton  , and small fish, respectively.   This
figure  corresponds to  a   situation in  which  the degree  of
perturbation in the growth rate, caused, for example by pollution,
is uncertain,  but is known  to  lie within some range.   The effect
of this uncertainty on the relative magnitudes of population
changes in the three trophic levels is shown.
                               20

-------
                                                                +5X
  50
               2000
4000       6000

  TIME IN DAYS
                                               8000
                                                          10000
Figure 6b

The  response  of  the  populations  in a  three-tiered  aquatic
ecosystem (measured in biomass per unit area, initial  biomass
ratios:   50 phytoplankton:  10 zooplankton :  1  small  fish) to +2%,
+3>5f, and +5% changes  in the rate at which fish die  off.   Solid,
dotted,  and (partially)  dashed lines give the  paths  for
phytoplankton, zooplankton  , and small fish,  respectively.   This
figure  corresponds to  a  situation  in  which the  degree  of
perturbation in the die-off rate is uncertain,  but is known to lie
within  some  range.    The  effect of this uncertainty on  the
relative magnitudes of population changes in the three trophic
levels is shown.
                               21

-------
75
                                                             -1%
                                                             -2%

                                                             -3%
                5000          10000

                           TIME IN DAYS
15000
20000
 Figure 6c

 The response of the populations in a  four-tiered aquatic ecosystem
 (measured in biomass per unit  area,  initial  biomass  ratios:   500
 phytoplankton:  100  zooplankton :  10 small fish: 1 larger fish) to
 -1%,  -2%, and  -3% changes in the  phytoplankton growth rate.    The
 paths for  the  responses of  the phytoplankton, zooplankton, small
 fish, and larger fish populations are given by the upper solid
 curve, the dotted curve, and partially  dashed curve, and the  lower
 solid curve, respectively.  This figure corresponds to a situation
 in which the degree of perturbation in the growth rate,  caused,
 for example by pollution,  is uncertain,  but is known to lie within
 some  range.   The  effect of this uncertainty on the relative
 magnitudes of population changes in the four  trophic levels is
 shown.
                                22

-------
nature study  (or the public itself, which occupies  the  top carnivore spot in



the global ecosystem!).    The  increase in error as it propagates up the chain



will  tend to render difficult the prediction of the magnitude of precisely



those effects that the public is most concerned about.  While an  enormous



effort is sometimes expended trying to determine  precisely the environmental



concentration of a pollutant,  the effort may be misplaced if error  propagation



leads to  large uncertainties higher up in the food chain where the public



welfare  is more directly and obviously involved.



   Like toxic substance  biomagnification, this magnification of  error is



unavoidable.   It is a consequence of the fundamental ecological dynamics of a



food  chain  and  can  not  be  circumvented.     Like  toxic  substance



biomagnification, whose effects at  the higher trophic levels  can be  minimized



by keeping the level of the  toxicant in the environment to a minimum, the



effect of error propagation up a food chain can be minimized by keeping to a



minimum the initial error in our knowledge of the effect of the toxicant on



the growth of the primary producers.



   We have  not  discussed here  the question raised  in the  Introduction



concerning the probability distribution of the quantity  of interest within its



range of uncertainty.   As mentioned previously, when a parameter  such as a



fish  population is uncertain,  but a  probability distribution for it is



calculable,   then  economic valuation is easier  than when such  a  probability



distribution  is unknown.   Consider an uncertainty in the effect of a toxicant



on the growth rate of a species of phytoplankton, as in our simple food  chain




model, that has the characteristic that the error  in our knowledge of  it is



gaussian-distributed.   What will  the distribution of biomagnified error  be in



the fish population?   Unfortunately, no general statement that is model-



independent  can  be made about  this  at  present.   The particular,  unabashedly



unrealistic,  model used to motivate  the existence of the phenomenon  of  error






                                    23

-------
biomagnification  provides a  precise answer to this question,  but other models



will generally provide other answers.   Because we lack confidence in any



particular model or class of  models  for the analysis of complex ecosystems,



further work is clearly needed  here.



   Since our ability to characterize  ecological uncertainty  with probability



distributions is presently limited, it might  seem like a sensible strategy for



ecologists to place more emphasis on  reducing the range of uncertainty.    As



we show in the following Section, that approach, too, has its limits  and,



indeed,  they  are  even more  stubborn than  are  the problems discussed



heretofore.






Refractory Error  in  Ecology



   Some types of uncertainty in impact assessment are easily remedied.   If a



few more observers spend a little more time  gathering data or improving their



models, a  noticeable  improvement will  result  and  these  remediable  types  of



errors will  be eliminated or at  least greatly  reduced  in magnitude.    A more



interesting class  of  errors can not be pushed to zero, however,  or  even



significantly reduced  in magnitude regardless  of  how much effort is expended



to do  so.    These are  the refractory   or  intrinsic uncertainties whose origin



we now discuss.    In a general sense,  they  stem from two  sources: uniqueness



and sensitivity  to Initial conditions.   We explain  these in turn.



   The uniqueness  of individual ecosystems and of the planetary environment in



its entirety renders  it impossible to achieve  the sina  qua non  of the



classical scientific experimental approach—replication of the system under



Investigation.    Without the benefit   of  replicable  systems,  a statistically



meaningful analysis of the effect of  a toxin on an  ecosystem is unattainable.



The reason is that in any  dose-response study, be it at  the level of an



individual organism or  at the ecosystem level,  one's  interest is always in the

-------
difference between a  treatment  and a control system.    Inherently,  this



requires at least two initially  identical systems.   If replication of the



treatment  and  control systems  is  also desired so that  a  measure of the



statistical  significance of the dose-response relarion  can be derived,  then



even more identical systems are required.   Ecosystems, unfortunately, are not



so obliging.   Two nearby lakes,  two forests  in the same  region, and even two



patches of meadow close by one  another differ  in myraid ways;  ecologists



will never  be aware of  all of them,  let alone be able  to quantify them.



   To attempt a resolution  of this dilemma,  interest in ecological microcosms



has recently accelerated.   Microcosms are segments of natural ecosystems of a.



size convenient  for laboratory  replication and analysis.    Lake microcosms,



for example,  consist of containers  filled  with lake  water  and possibly lake



sediments  taken from a real lake.    If appropriate precautions are taken



in  the  design,  initiation, and operation  of these systems,  they can be



replicated adequately for periods of  up to several  months and used for



toxicological  testing.   Because they can be put together in such a way that a



large fraction of the  natural  ecological diversity in the parent system is



present in the microcosms,  they  offer a partial solution  to the problem of



uniqueness.   Valuable as the microcosm approach  is for  ecotoxicological



testing, problems of size  or scale inherently limit its usefulness.   Most



importantly,  it is not feasible to place large plants an animals in  them; to



do  so would result  in wildly unrealistic  behavior,  both with respect to



chemical  concentrations and  population densities in  the microcosms.



Therefore,  the very types of organisms of greatest interest to the public can



not be  studied  in such  systems.   In addition,  long-term microcosm



investigations  (usually of more than a few months duration) are  not  possible



without  jeopardizing the ecological realism (that is,  the degree of similarity



between  the control microcosms and the parent ecosystem  from which the






                                   25

-------
microcosms were derived)  of  the microcosms.



   Which  brings  us to  the second refractory  source  of uncertainty—



sensitivity to initial conditions.   Ecosystems,  like the global climate



system,  are complex at many  spatial and temporal  dimensions.    That is,  within



such systems microscopic behavior and  macroscopic  behavior are  present and are



strongly coupled.    For  example,  the population dynamics of microbes can



affect the health of fish  in a lake,  and at a molecular level, the diffusion



of  nutrients  and  the turbulence  of  the water  can  affect  the microbe



populations.   In the global  climate system, atmospheric turbulence influences



climate on a macroscopic  scale.    In systems where  such different dimensions



are coupled and chaotic or  turbulent behavior is important,  the ability to



predict the future  consequences of the system is severly limited.    In  a



profound analysis  of the  effect of turbulence on climate prediction,  Lorenz



(1969) showed  that microscopic turbulence introduces an intrinsic source of



error in the  prediction process.    In particular,  it renders the  future



behavior of the climate incredibly  sensitive to initial  conditions.   The



amount of detailed initial conditions one needs to measure in order to predict



future climate with any specified degree of accuracy increases faster than



exponentially  with the period of time into the future one wants to predict the



climate.   Long term prediction with the same detail  and accuracy as we now



can  achieve  for one or  two day  predictions  thus becomes  intrinsically



impossible for a practical reason: we can not gather sufficiently detailed



measurements on  today's climate.



   The deep  reason  for this  phenomenon is the extreme  sensitivity of complex



systems possessing many scales of motion, such as systems with turbulence,  to



small changes  in initial conditions.   Platt et al. (1977) investigated marine



ecosystems and found a similar sensitivity  to  initial conditions.    It is



likely, in  fact,  that ecosystems, generally,  are characterized by  such  a






                                   26

-------
sensitivity, although this has not  been investigated yet.





Conclusion



   The major advances in environmentally relevant ecological research in the



past decade have not been in the  direction of developing models  that can
 *


predict with greater accuracy  the future state of a disturbed ecosystem or the



distribution  of values of some uncertain parameter within  its  range of



uncertainty.   Rather the direction of progress has been in characterizing the



features of ecosystems  that render them either  vulnerable or  susceptible to



change  when subjected to stress  and  in identifying the major sources of



uncertainty.   Rather than making substantial progress in the  development of



one "correct" mathematical model for predicting the future behavior of an



ecosystem, the effort has been to search for relatively model-independent



truths.   Valuable  as this information is, it does not necessarily provide the



type of information economists need if they are to apply  valuation procedures



to realistic situations.    Error propagation and the  existence of refractory



sources of uncertainty in ecology must  be  taken into account if realistic



goals for benefit-cost  analysis in environmental policy are to be set. Perhaps



most importantly, uncertainty  about uncertainty—that is, uncertainty about



the probability distribution of  ecological variables within their range of



uncertainty—limits progress  toward more rational decision making.    Perhaps



error distributions can be better characterized and  refractory uncertainties



can be  reduced by more  intensive analysis  of ensembles  of models in



conjunction with properly designed laboratory and field  studies.   In any



event,  progress toward the  goal  of  more rational  decision making  will



require that economists and ecologists working  at the  interface  of these two



discriplines are aware of  the  internal  constraints  of each  others' field,



while at the same time  they sharpen their tools within their own.
                                    27

-------
References
Cairns,   J.,  and  J.  Harte,  1985.    "The  Myth of  the  Threshold  in
   Ecotoxicology", in preparation.

Lorenz,  E., 1969.    "The Predictability of a Flow Which Possesses Many Scales
   of Motion".   Tellus 21.  (3), pp. 289-307.

Platt, T., K. Denham,  and A. Jasby, 1977.   "Modelling the Productivity of
   Phytoplankton", in The Seas; Ideas and  Observations on Progress in the
   Study  of the Seas. E.  Goldberg, ed. Vol. 6. Wiley, N.Y.,  N.Y..

Reckhow,  K.,  198M.    "Decision  Theory Applied to  Lake  Management",  Duke
   University School of Forestry and Environmental Studies,  Durham, N.C..

Roth, P., C. Blanchard, J. Harte, H. Michaels,  and M. El-Ashry, 1985.   "The
   American West's Acid Rain",  World  Resources  Institute,  Research Report #1.
   Washington, D.C..

U. S. Executive Order 12291,  1981.
                                   28

-------
                                  Chapter  5
               Hysteresis,  Uncertainty,  and  Economic  Valuation

                              I.   INTRODUCTION

     The purpose of this  chapter  is  to  investigate some issues  that arise
when one attempts to conduct a benefit  evaluation for the control  of pol-
lution in an aquatic ecosystem.   Obviously,  the extent of the benefits de-
pends on the nature of the  ecosystem's  response to control.   We are concerned
with two aspects of ecosystem behavior  in  particular.  The first is the
phenomenon known as "hysteresis", as discussed  in chapter 3.   Recall that
this is the notion that a damaged ecosystem may not respond immediately to
a cessation in pollution  discharges  and, when it does respond,  may not
exactly retrace the trajectory of its decline.   Indeed, because of some
irrecoverable losses from the system, it may never return to its original
state.  The second aspect of ecosystem  behavior we focus on is  the stochas-
ticity of natural phenomena which, as emphasized in chapter 4,  implies that
the ecosystem response is inherently uncertain.
     Both the uncertainty and the dynamic constraints on ecosystem behavior
need to be taken into account in evaluating the benefits of control and in
the related decision on whether, or when, to control.  Recovery dynamics, for
example, may favor doing nothing, as in the case where the system is so far
gone that recovery is impossible, or they may favor early action precisely
to  forestall more damaging,  long-lasting consequences.
     When uncertainty is factored into the analysis, an additional considera-
tion arises which is sometimes overlooked.  The temporal resolution of uncertainty-
                                     -1-

-------
the possibility of acquiring better  information  about  the  future consequences



of controlling or continuing pollution—adds an  extra  element to the decision



calculus.  Regardless of whether the decisionmaker  exhibits  risk aversion or



risk neutrality, if further information is  forthcoming,  there is a premium on



those initial actions which preserve future flexibility  and  a discount  on those



which reduce flexibility and preclude the exploitation of  the additional infor-



mation at a later date.  In the present context, this  could  be  information



about either the dynamics of ecosystem behavior  or  the social valuation of eco-



system products.  If we control pollution now and,  subsequently, learn  that the



ecosystem was not at a threshold of  irreversible damage, we  can always  resume



pollution later; but if we do not control now and then observe  irreversible



changes in the ecosystem, we cannot  undo them by controlling later.  Similarly,



if we control now and then learn that future generations place  a low value on



ecosystem services, we can resume pollution;  but if we do  not control now and



the ecosystem is irreversibly damaged, it is too late  to act if we  subsequently



discover that future generations place a high value on the ecosystem.   In each



case there is an asymmetry in our ability to exploit future  information and a



premium associated with the action that preserves flexibility.



    This flexibility premium has been recognized in the  environmental valuation



literature under the name of "quasi  option  value" (Arrow and Fisher  [1974]) or



"option value"  (Henry [1974]).   Within the context of an  irreversible  land



development decision where the future benefits of preservation  in an unde-



veloped state are uncertain, these authors  show that,  when a decisionmaker



ignores the possibility of acquiring further information about  the  future



value of undeveloped land, he inevitably understates the net benefit of preser-



vation over development and prejudices the  decision somewhat in favor of im-



mediate development.



                                      -2-

-------
    The present wo^k  extends  these  results  in several ways.  First, we con-
sider a decision framework where the irreversibility is associated with not
taking action now (i.e.,  not controlling):   In effect, we are dealing with the
sin of omission rather than  commission.  More importantly, we consider a multi-
period decision problem,  rather than the two-period problem of previous work.
This change is important  not merely  because  it is a step in the direction of
greater realism--most practical policy issues involve a sequence of decision
points—but also because  it  enables  us to  investigate some questions that are
obscured within a two-period framework.
    Suppose continued stress on a  system is  certain to trigger irreversible
changes, beyond some critical  point  or period, but we do not know the period.
Is there an analog to the two-period option  value?  Or suppose the critical
period is known, but the damaging  consequences are delayed as with certain
kinds of health impacts.  How does this affect the control decision?  Still
another issue we can consider in a multiperiod setting is the distinction
between ordinary lags and irreversibility.   Irreversible environmental de-
gradation may be regarded as an extreme form of .a lagged recovery in which the
lag period is infinite (or,  at any rate, longer than the effective planning
horizon).  What about less extreme lags where, if pollution continues beyond a
certain point, the ecosystem is disabled for a certain (finite) period of time
but  then recovers:  Do the option  value arguments still apply?
    Uncertainty, or more precisely the nature of learning, is necessarily
treated differently in a multiperiod setting.  In the two-period models, un-
certainty is assumed completely resolved by  the start of the second period.
By contrast, we assume that the decisionmaker acquires some, but not all of
the  information over the first period, more  over the second, more still over
                                      -3-

-------
the third, and so on.   Partial,  not perfect,  information at any time is



accordingly part of the structure of our  model.



     The chapter is organized as follows:   In the  next section we develop a



model to evaluate pollution control, taking account of both the relevant



physical constraints and the uncertainties.  The model is used in sections



III and IV to study the implications of various  interesting combinations of



recovery dynamics and uncertainties, of the sort just noted.  Conclusions



are offered in section V.







            II.  A FRAMEWORK FOR BENEFIT EVALUATION AND DECISION





     We model the decision on whether or not to  control pollution from the



point of view of an environmental authority concerned with the net present



value (benefits minus costs) of control.   The optimal control is defined as



the choice that maximizes this value.  The important contraints are those



that emerge from the discussion of the preceding section:  (1) Beyond some
                                     -4-

-------
point in time, failure to control  is not readily reversible; and (2) the



benefits of control are uncertain due to a lack of knowledge about the timing



and nature of ecosystem recovery and the willingness of individuals to pay for



the goods and services it can produce.



    Though recovery is a continuous process, evaluation and control take place



in a discrete setting.  Thus, we assume that a decision to control pollution



can be made in each period t =  1,  2, 3,  	  The outcome of the decision can



be represented by a sequence X,, X2, X3,  ..., where X. = 1 corresponds to



building a treatment plant, say, and X  = 0 corresponds to not building.  Note



that we are considering a binary choice, neglecting intermediate levels of



control.  The results we obtain can be extended to the case of continuous con-



trol, but this is somewhat beside  the point and comes at a substantial cost in



complexity.



    Associated with the choice  of  Xt  is a set of benefits and costs.  The



capital and operating costs of  the control  facility in period t are denoted by



Ct, and the benefits are denoted Bt; the net benefits are NB  = B  - C .  In



the most general model, the benefits and costs accruing during any time period



depend not only on the current  pollution  control decision, X , but also on



all previous decisions, X,, ..., Xt_p



    An essential feature mentioned above  is that the benefits and costs of



ecosystem recovery are uncertain.  Thus, we write the overall net benefit



function as






 NB(X1,X2,X3, ...; 9) = NB^Xp- 6) +  6 NB2(XpX2; 0) + &2 NB3(XpX2,X3; 0) + ..
                                    -5-

-------
where




     NBt(X1, ..., Xt; 6) = Bt(X1,  ...,  Xt; 6)  -  Ct(Xp  ..







Here 8 is a one-period discount  factor,  and 0  is a  random variable  (or vector



of random variables) representing  the present  uncertainty concerning  the  fu-



ture consequences of pollution control.



    With regard to the cost functions,  it seems  reasonable  to assume  that,



with probability 1,





                              Ct(0, ..., 0; 9) = 0





and






               Li. ^ A-i , . . . , ^* _ i > 1 > 9 J  ^  f^  1 '  •••>   t_1>   ' « J •







That is to say, pollution control  is costly.   Finally,  in order to  keep the



decision problem simple while still making it  interesting,  we focus on a  three-



period model.  This is significantly more general than the  two-period models



which have been used  in irreversibility literature  so far  (for example, Arrow



and Fisher [1974], Henry [1974], Epstein [1980]).  With minimal notational



clutter, it permits us to consider scenarios involving a variety  of types of



irreversibility, which is our primary objective in  this paper.



    Given this structure, the social decision problem is to maximize  the  dis-



counted present value of expected net benefits:






 (1)                        max    E{NB(X,, X7, X,;  9)}.
                                        1.   £.    j
                                    -6-

-------
Two aspects of this problem need to be addressed, both pertaining  to the treat-
ment of uncertainty.   First, what about attitudes toward risk?  Should one
assume risk aversion on the part of the social decisionmaker  and,  therefore,
include a risk-premium term when taking the expectation in  (1), or should one
assume risk neutrality following the arguments,  for example,  of Samuelson
[1964] or Arrow and Lind [1970]?  Although it clearly makes a difference in
practice, the question of risk aversion is not fundamental  to the  results that
we will obtain:  They are qualitatively independent of any  assumption about
risk preferences.  The second aspect of modeling uncertainty  in a  dynamic set-
ting is its behavior over time.  Uncertainty means a lack of  information; yet,
it  is likely that this situation changes—that  information  is acquired over
time.  Our analysis is largely concerned  with the consequences of  a failure on
the part of the decisionmaker to take this prospect  into account.  We will
show how this affects the social decision and how conventional benefit-cost
analysis must be adjusted to incorporate  this consideration.
    Suppose, first, that the decisionmaker does  not have to commit himself in
the first period to an entire intertemporal  control  strategy; he  can postpone
the choice of X2 to t = 2 and the choice  of  X, to t  =  3.  Suppose, moreover,
that  in each time period (except t = 3),  he  recognizes that further informa-
tion  about the future consequences of control will become available which he
can exploit in making these future decisions.  Define
 (2a)                V3(X3|X1, X2) E E3{NB3(Xlf X2,  X3;  9)}
 (2b)        V2(X2|X1) = E2(NB2(X1, X£; 0) + max 6 V^X^,  X2)>
                                             X3
                                      -7-

-------
(2c)              V^X^  E E^NB^X^ 6) + max 3

                                           X
where E  {•} denotes  an expectation with respect to the information set avail-

able at time t--i.e., E,  is  the expectation with respect to the decision-

maker's prior distribution for 6, £2  is the expectation with respect to his

posterior distribution in t  = 2 which is updated in a Bayesian manner on the

basis of the information  obtained by  the beginning of the second period, etc.

One point must be emphasized:  We assume that the acquisition of information

does not depend on the choice of X  ;  it emerges either with the passage of

time (e.g., as period 2 approaches, one can make a more accurate assessment

about the social value of environmental quality in the second period) or as

the result of a separate  research program on ecosystem dynamics.
    •
    Following the Backwards  Induction Principle of dynamic programming, in the

third period the decisionmaker selects


(3a)                      X3  = arg max V^^, X£),


in the second he selects


(3b)                        X2  E arg  max V^X^X^,



and in the first he selects


(3c)                         X:  =  arg max V^).



    In each case we are assuming  that, however X,, ..., X  , are chosen, Xf is

chosen optimally in the light of  these previous decisions.  Where it is neces-
                                                 S*
sary to emphasize this dependence,  we shall write X   as an explicit function of
                                     -8-

-------
the previous choice  variables--e.g., X  = X-(X ).  In the terminology of sto-
chastic control theory,  (X.., X?, X,) represents a closed-loop policy:  At each
decision point, both current information and all future anticipated  informa-
tion are considered  in choosing a control.
    We wish to contrast  this with a policy  in which the prospect of  future
information is disregarded.  There  are two ways to model this.  One  is to as-
sume that, although the  decisionmaker  is still free to postpone his  choice of
X? and X, until the  second and third periods, respectively, in each period
 Lf      J
he ignores the possibility of  future learning and deals with uncertainty about
future consequences  by replacing random variables with his current estimate of
their mean.  Define
(4a)                 V3(X3lXi>  V  =  E3{NB3(X1'  X2»  X3;
 (4b)       V2(X2|X1) = max E^NB^X^  X2;  9)  +  6  NB^Xj,  X2,  X3;  e)}
                       X
(4c)  v(X1) =  max  E^NB^X^  9)  +  B NB2(Xp  X£;  0)  +  6  NB3(Xp X2> X3;  e)}
               X2'X3
 In the third period, the decisionmaker selects

 (5a)                      X* = arg max V*(X3|X1,  X2):

 in the second he selects

 (5b)                        X* = arg  max V^X^X^,

 and in the first he selects

 (5c)                         X* = arg max V*(X1).

                                     -9-

-------
In the terminology of stochastic control  theory,  this  is an  open-loop  feedback


policy:  As new information becomes  available, the decisionmaker  incorporates


it in his choice of a control;  but he assumes  that no  further  information will


become available.


    The other approach to modeling the disregard  of  future  information is to


assume that the decisionmaker does not wait  (or cannot wait) until  the second


and third periods to choose X2  anc* X, but,  instead,  chooses  them  in the first


period along with X,.  This decision, denoted  (X,  ,  X_ , X,  ),  is the  solution to
(6)      max    E1{NB1(X1; 6) + B NB2(Xp  X2;  9)  + 62  NB3(\1,  X2,  X3;  8)}.


       X1'X2'X3
This  is known as an open-loop control where all decisions are made simul-



taneously on the basis of the information available at the beginning of  the

                                                          A    &A
initial period.  Comparing (5) and (6), it is clear that X, = X.  , but in



general, X~  / X- and X,  / X,--there is no difference between the open-loop



and open-loop feedack controls in the first period but in subsequent periods

                                                               /\       j.

they  differ.  Thus our discussion below of the relation between X, and X-,  also



applies to X, , but it does not apply to relations in t = 2 and t = 3.



Since, in a three-period model, unlike a two-period model, the choice of X- is



of substantive interest, the sharp distinction between open-loop  and open-loop



feedback policies is one of the benefits that we gain by switching to a  multi-



period setting.  It will become clear below that, for our purposes, useful  re-



sults can be obtained by comparing the closed-loop policy with the open-loop



feedback policy.



    We can pursue this comparison in two ways.  We can ask a policy question:



How do X  and X  differ?  In particular, under what circumstances is it
        t      U
          S\     £

true  that Xt >_ X  (i.e., the case for intervening to control pollution is
                                      -10-

-------
strengthened when the prospect of  further  information  is recognized)?  Or we

                                               ^          A
can ask a benefit evaluation question:  How do  V  (•) and V (•) differ?  What


correction is required when expected benefits are estimated by replacing un-


certain future quantities with a current estimate of their expected value?


    Given the constraint that X  = 0 or 1, these  questions can be answered by


observing that, from (2)-(4),




(7a)                  Xx >_ (<) X*      as      OV1 >_ (•<) 0




and, for any given X,,





(7b)             LCX,) > (<) X*(Xn)     as     OV?(X,) > (<) 0
                  £  J.  ~"  ~"   "   _L               L* ±. "~"  ""^



where




(8a)                 OV1 = [VjU)  - V^O)] -  [V*(l) -  V*(0)j
(8b)                     = [^(1) - V*(l)]  -  [V^O)  - V*(0)];
and, given X-,,




(9a)        OV




(9b)
The quantities 0V, and OV_(X.) are the correction factors  required when the pros-


pect of future information is disregarded and benefits  are measured  in terms of

 *               ~
VtO) instead of Vt(»); they are multiperiod generalizations  of  the  Arrow-


Fisher-Henry concept of option value.
                                     -11-

-------
                                                                        ^

    To interpret them,  consider  (8b) and  (9b) and observe that the term [V (X ) -
V.(X )] can be cast in the  form of
(10)     Vt(») - V*(»)  =  Et{  max    Ft(-;6)}-   max   Et{Ft(.;8)}.
This is a measure of the  value of  information acquired after the beginning of


period t that can be exploited  in  the  subsequent  choice  of X   ,, X  2>  •••>

                                                              •"•         *
conditional on the choice of  X   in period t.  Thus,  in (8b), [V,(l) - V,(l)]


is the expected value of  the  information that might  be acquired in time to in-


fluence the second- and third-period choices conditional on controlling pollution

                            s*.       £
in the first period, while [V,(0)  -  V,(0)]  is the expected value of sub-


sequent information conditional  on not controlling pollution in the first period.


The correction factor 0V, is  simply the difference between these two condi-


tional values of information; similarly, for OV_. Thus, if 0V >^ 0, the value


of information associated with  setting X  = 1 exceeds that associated with a


decision to set X  = 0 and the case for controlling  pollution  in period t is


strengthened when the prospect  of  future information is  considered.  Conversely,


if 0V. <_Q, the case for pollution control  is weakened.


    However, without placing further structure  on the model, it is impossible to


determine which outcome is the more likely. From the convexity of the maximum


operator and Jensen's Inequality applied to (10), it follows that Vt(») -


V (•) >^ 0.  Thus, each component of 0V  is  nonnegative;  but this tells us


nothing about the sign of their difference. In the  following  sections we con-


sider some alternative model structures embodying features of  ecosystem dynamics


discussed  in section II and explore their effect on  0V   and their implications


for pollution control policy.
                                     -12-

-------
                   III.  CRITICAL PERIOD IRREVERSIBILITY






    Suppose that,  at  some point in the evolution of the ecosystem, if the



policymaker does not  intervene and control pollution at that time, it could



never be optimal for  him to control pollution subsequently.  We shall call a



time period with this property a  "critical" period.  Whether such a phenomenon



exists and what factors bring it  about depends on the specifics of the eco-



system structure.  In the context of  the three-period model, suppose that,



while it might pay to introduce controls after pollution has continued un-



checked for one more  period,  it could never pay to  introduce controls after



pollution has continued unchecked for two more periods in a row.  More for-



mally, we assume that, with probability 1,





(11)        Et(NB3(0, 0, 1; 0)} <_ Et{NB3(0, 0, 0; 9)}          t = 2, 3.






Thus, if pollution is not controlled  in the first period (X, = 0), the second



period becomes critical.



    From (2a,b) and (4b), when X, = 0, we have






(12a)  V2(0|0) = E2{NB2(0, 0; 6)  + 0  max  [E3 NB3(0, 0, 1; 0), E3 NB3(0, 0, 0; 9)]},








(12b)  V*(0|0) = E2 NB2(0, 0; 6)  + 0  max  [E£ NB3(0, 0, 1; 6), EZ NB3(0, 0, 0; 9)].






Applying (11) yields





(13a)        V2(0|0)  = E2 NB2(0,  0; 9) + 0 E2(E3 NB3(0, 0, 0; 9)}.








(13b)        V*(0|0)  = E2 NB2(0,  0; 6) + 6 E£ NB3(0, 0, 0; 0).
                                    -13-

-------
However, by the Total Probability Theorem, Et{h(e)} = Et(E    h(e)} for any



function of a random variable, h(e).  Therefore, we obtain the key result that







(14)                        V2(0|0)  - V*(0|0) = 0.







Because the second period is critical when X, =0, it follows that, if the



decisionmaker does not control pollution in that period, he anticipates that



he will never choose to control  it  subsequently.  Since the anticipated future



decisions are exactly the same under  both the closed-loop and open-loop feed-



back policies, the expected future  benefits are  identical under both policies.



In effect, any subsequent information is expected to have no economic value



because it is not anticipated  to have any effect on future decisions; hence,



(14).  Substituting this into  (9) yields






(15)                    OV2(0)  = V2(l|0) - V*(l|0) >_ 0.








From (7b), this implies that X2(0)  ^X2(0).  That  is,  if pollution is not con-



trolled in the first period, we have  a  situation where, once the  potential for



the acquisition of future information is recognized, the case for controlling



pollution in the second period is  strengthened,  and there  is a positive flexi-



bility premium associated with setting  X2 = 1.



    The key to this analysis is equation (11) which embodies our  particular as-



sumption that the second period is critical when X, =  0.  Without imposing any



additional restrictions, it is impossible to determine the signs  of OV-^ or OV7(1)



For example, from (11), one cannot  infer that V2(0|l)  = V2(0|l).  Therefore,



the indeterminacy concerning the relation between  X, and X,, or X2(l) and



X,(1), remains.
                                    -14-

-------
    Generalizing from this  particular example, a period  is critical whenever an



equation analogous  to (11)  holds,  i.e., whenever the situation  is such that, if



the decisionmaker does not  control in that period, with  probability 1 he antici-



pates that it would never pay  to control  in future periods regardless of the



information subsequently acquired.  By  construction, when a  period t  is critical,


                   *                                                 *
we have V (0|») = V (OH which implies that 0V  (•) >  0  and  X  (•) > X.(-).
         U         C                           L    ^"         L.    *""   L


    It may be useful to compare our notion of a critical period with  the concept



of irreversibility employed by Arrow and Fisher  [1974] and by Henry [1974] which,



in the present context, would  be represented by a constraint of the form





(16)                          X, = 0 -»•  X7 > X,.
                               J_          £ —   ^






Our assumption (11) implies (16) but is somewhat broader and illuminates the



two crucial ingredients required to extend their results to  more general



settings.  First, what is irreversible  is the policy,  not the fate of any



particular biotic components.   The ecosystem dynamics  may be such that, if



X2 = 0, the lake trout become  extinct without this necessarily  implying (11)



as long as the trout are sufficiently  unimportant relative to  the decision-



maker's other objectives.   The truth or falsity of (11)  depends on values as



well as biology.  Second, what is  at issue is economic rather  than technical



irreversibility.  The technology may be such that the  decision  on X2  is



physically reversible in later periods  (e.g., setting  X^ = 0 corresponds to



permitting the construction of a steel  mill on  the edge  of a lake which could



subsequently be converted to a nonpolluting bowling alley);  the question is



whether it could ever pay to reverse the, current decision.   Moreover, what



matters is the present anticipation of whether  it could  ever pay to reverse
                                     -15-

-------
that decision.   Our  assumption (11) does not preclude the possibility that,



ex post, at the end  of period 3,  it might actually turn out that it would have



been optimal to choose X3 = 1 even with X2 = 0.  What is required is that,



ex ante, this choice is always deemed implausible.  Thus, we can admit the



possibility that





                      NB3(0, 0,  l; 9) > NB3(0, 0, 0; 9)






for some realizations of 9 as long as the prior density on 9 and the subse-



quent updated posterior densities are sufficiently bounded to ensure that the



expected benefits satisfy the inequality in (11).






                  IV .  DELAYED AND TEMPORARY IRREVERSIBILITY





    In this section  we consider two forms of irreversibility which are weaker



than the critical-period concept  introduced above and yield somewhat different



results.  First, we  consider what might be called "delayed" irreversibility:



If pollution is not  controlled, the consequences are (economically) irrevers-



ible, but the irreversibility sets in only after a lag.  Thus, if pollution is



permitted to continue now,  there  is an intermediate period during which it may



or may not be optimal to impose controls; but, after this intermediate period,



it can never pay to control.  Within the framework of our three-period model,



we identify "now" with period 1,  the intermediate period during which it may



or may not be optimal to control  with period 2, and the subsequent future with



period 3.  The assumption of delayed irreversibility is captured by combining



(11) together with the assumption that






(17)         Et(NB3(0, 1,  1; 6)}  <_ Et(NB3(0, 1, 0; 9)}     t = 2, 3
                                    -16-

-------
with probability 1.   The question  to  be addressed  is how  this  type of  irre-


versibility affects  the  pollution-control decision in period 1.


    Substituting (11) and (17)  into (2c) and  (4c)  yields  the following expres-


sions for V^O) and  V*(0):




    V1(0) = El NB1(0; 9) +  3 EX {max  [E2 NB2(0,  0; 0) + 8 EZ NB3(0, 0, 0;  9),


(18a)

            E2 NB2(0, 1; 9) + 3 E2 NB3(0,  1,  0;  9)]}





      V*(0) = EL NB^O;  9)  * 3 max [EL NB2(0, 0; 9) + 3 E: NB,(0, 0, 0; e),


(18b)

              E: NB2(0,  1;  9) + 3  ^  NB3(0,  1, 0;  9)].



                                          *         f.
By inspection, it can be seen that, while V,(0)  -  Vl(0) ^ 0, it  is not true

                ~        *                                       ~
in general that V,(0) = V,(0).   Since it can also  be shown that  V,(l)  -


V1(l) >_ 0, from (8a,b),  this is a  situation  where  the sign of  0V, and  the  re-

               ~       *
lation between X, and X, are indeterminate.
                                 XV
    Observe that the formula for V^O)  in  (18a)  involves  information acquired


between the first and second periods  but not that  acquired between the second


and third periods—the expectation £,{•} does not  appear.  The latter  informa-


tion has no economic value when X, =  0  because the irreversibility has set in by


then, but the former does have some value  because  it can  be exploited  during the


intermediate period (t = 2) where  there is still some flexibility.  Of course,


if X, = 1, there is sufficient flexibility to exploit both sets  of information.


But this fact, by itself, does not guarantee that  the overall  value of informa-


tion associated with setting X, =  1 necessarily  exceeds that associated with


setting X  = 0.  The point is that, with delayed irreversibility, the  first
                                     -17-

-------
period is not critical  because,  if one does not control, then it is not^ true
that it can never be optimal to  control  subsequently;  it may still be optimal
to control during the intervening period before the irreversibility sets in.
Thus, with delayed irreversibility,  the  introduction of future learning into
the decision calculus need not tilt  the  balance in favor of immediate control.
    We now examine what might be called  "temporary" irreversibility as opposed
to the "permanent" irreversibility considered so far.  We consider two
scenarios.  In the first we suppose  that,  if pollution is not controlled in
any period, the consequences are temporarily irreversible and are felt in the
following period but not necessarily thereafter.  In effect, the system has a
one-period memory with

(19)                  Et{NB2(0,  1;  0)}  < Et{NB2(0, 0;  0)}

(20a)       NB3(X2> X3' Q) E NB3(°»  X2>  X3' e) = ^(l, X2, X3; 8)

(20b)                 Et(NB3(0,  1;  6)}  <_ Et  {NB3(0, 0; 9)}.


In this case V.(0) and V,(0) are given by

 VjCO) * El NB1(0; 6) + 6 E^max^ NB2(0, 1; 6) + & EZ max [E3 NB3(1, 0; 0),
(21a)
         E3 NB3(1, 1; 0)], E2 NB2(0, 0;  0) + 6 EZ NB3(0, 0; 0)J \  ,


     V*(0) = EJ_ NB1(0; 0) + 6 max {El NB2(0, 1; 0) + 6 max  [EX NBjCl, 0; 0),
(21b)
             Ex NB3(1, 1; 0)], Ej_ NB2(0, 0; 0) + 6 EI  NB3(0, 0; 0)]}.
                                    -18-

-------
It follows that, while V^O)  - V*(0) >_ 0,  it  is not true  in general that V,(0) =


V.(0).  Thus, with this type  of temporary  irreversibility, the sign of 0V  and

                     *       A
the relation between X, and X, are indeterminate.


    We now change the scenario by assuming that,  if pollution is not con-


trolled in the first period,  the consequences are temporarily irreversible in


the second period but the third period is  entirely independent of what has hap-


pened previously, i.e., the system makes a fresh  start and has no memory in the


third period.  Thus, we retain (19) while  assuming that the third-period bene-


fit functions satisfy the restrictions
                   NB3(X3; 6)  =  NB3(1,  1,  X3;  8)  =  NB3(1,  0,  X3;  e)

(22)

                              =  NB3(0,  1,  X3;  6)  =  NB3(0,  0,  X3;  e).



                     ~          *
The new formulas for V,(0) and V,(0)  are




               VL(0) = Ej_ NBjCO; 9)  + 6 El NB2(0, 0;  e)


(23a)


                     '  + B2 Ej_ {max  [E3 NB3(0; e),  Ej NB3(1;  e)]}





                V*(0) = El NB1(0; 9)  + 6 Ej_ NB2(0,  0; 9)


(23b)


                        + 62 max [E1  NB3(0; 9), EI  NB3(1;  9)].




Similarly, substitution of (19)  and  (22) into  (2c)  and (4c) yields the  following


formulas for V^l) and V*(l):
                                    -19-

-------
      V^l) = El  NB1(1;  6) + 6 EI  {max  [E£ NB2(1, 0; e), EZ NB2(1, 1; 9)]}


(24a)


              + B2  Ex  (max [E3 NB3(0; 9), ES NBjCl; 9)]}
        V1(l) = Ex NB1(1;  9)  +  B max  [EX NB2(1, 0; 9), EX NB2(1,  1; 9)]


(24b)


                + B2 max [Ex  NB3(0; 9), EI NBj(l; 9)].





In this case, although it  is  still true that  [V^l)  - V*(l)] ^0  and  [V



V,(0)] ^ 0, we can determine  the sign of 0V.  since application of (8) yields



              OV1 = 0 Ex {max [E2 NB2(1, 0; 9), EZ NB2(1, 1; 9]}


(25)

                    - B max [Ej_ NB2(1, 0; 9),  EX NB2(1,  1;  9)] >_  0.



                           ^    *
It follows, therefore, that X,  >_X,.


    In the first scenario, based on  (19) and  (20a,b),  if one fails to control


in the first period, it may nevertheless be optimal  to control in the second,


despite the irreversibility embodied  in (19),  because  second-period decisions


influence third-period outcomes.  Thus, when  X, = 0, information  acquired


between the first and second  periods  still has some  economic value because it


may shed light on third-period outcomes and can, therefore, affect the second-


period decision.  When X,  = 1,  information acquired  between the first and


second periods also has an economic  value.  Consequently, the  net effect of


incorporating future learning into benefit estimation  is ambiguous:  it may


strengthen or weaken the case for  initial control.
                                     -20-

-------
    By contrast, in the second scenario, based on (19) and  (22), the  second-



period decision cannot affect  third-period outcomes at all  because of the



total lack of memory between these two periods.  Therefore,  the  temporary



irreversibility in (19) ensures that  it is never optimal to control in the



second period when one has not also controlled in the first. As a result,  the



information acquired between the first and second periods has some value when



X, = 1 but none when X, = 0.  Moreover, because the system  makes a fresh start



in the third period, the information  acquired between the second and  third



periods is equally valuable regardless of whether X  = 0 or 1, t=l, 2.



Hence, the case for initial control is unambiguously strengthened when one



recognizes the possibility of future  learning.



    While it is clear that the first  scenario of temporary  irreversibility  is



incompatible with the concept of a critical  period, the  second  scenario can



still be related to that concept, albeit in  a somewhat unusual manner.  Under



the second scenario,  if the decisionmaker decides not to control in the first



period, he anticipates that it could  never be optimal for him to reverse this



decision during the subsequent interval lasting until the  system's memory  is



"reset."  Once that has occurred, all future decisions are  entirely



independent of prior  events.  Thus, there is a  sense  in  which the  first period



is "locally" critical.





                                V. CONCLUSIONS





    It has long been  recognized that  the selection of an optimal pollution



control or other environmental policy is highly dependent  on the treatment  of



time and uncertainty  in the benefit cost calculus.  A delay in  ecosystem



recovery, for example, may reduce the present value  of  the  benefits from
                                   -21-

-------
control;  but if the recovery lags caused by continuing pollution are growing
faster than the discount  rate, this would tilt the balance in favor of early
control,  as shown in a somewhat  different context by Krutilla and Fisher
(1975).  Similarly, depending upon one's view of the degree of risk aversion
appropriate for public policy decisions, the presence of uncertainty may
require an adjustment to  the expected monetary benefits and costs of control.
Since there may be uncertainty about  the consequences of both control and no
control,  this could cut either way.
    While not denying the importance  of these  issues for empirical policy
analysis, in this chapter we have  focused on a different aspect of benefit
evaluation involving flexibility,  the temporal resolution of uncertainty, and
the value of information.  In a  dynamic system,  information about the conse-
quences of previous actions may  arrive over time, and this prospect must be
taken into consideration  when one makes policy decisions.  Future observations
have no economic value, however, if (1) they are entirely uninformative in the
sense that the prior and  posterior  distributions coincide or (2) they are
informative but they cannot affect subsequent  decisions because the policy-
maker lacks freedom of action.   Thus,  flexibility is a necessary ingredient
for information to have economic value.  This  must  be borne in mind when one
contemplates an action with irreversible consequences, because the resulting
lack of flexibility nullifies the value of any subsequent information.
    In many pollution control issues  this may be a  relevant consideration be-
cause the ecological consequences of a failure to control may be irreversible.
Actually, we have shown that what  is  crucial is  economic irreversibility.
That is to say, if in some time  period the decisionmaker anticipates that,
unless he controls then,  it would  never pay to control in the future,
                                    -22-

-------
regardless of the subsequent information, a decision not to control then would
effectively eliminate future flexibility.  In  that  case, there  is a positive
flexibility premium associated with a decision to control:  When future learn-
ing is taken into account,  the balance  is tilted  in favor  of  control.  We have
termed this a critical-period irreversibility.  In  other cases, however, the
issue is less clear cut.   For example,  it may  happen that  the irreversible
consequences are delayed  in their onset or are only temporary in their effects.
In such cases, we show that the  conditional value of future  information when
one fails to control now  is not  necessarily zero; conceivably it may exceed
the value of information  associated with a decision to control.  The prospect
of future learning then has an ambiguous effect--it may strengthen or weaken
the case for control.  Our intuition  is that the  value of  information condi-
tional on control will ordinarily exceed the value  of information conditional
on no control but this is an empirical  issue to be  resolved  through specific
case studies.  Such an application is the focus of  our current  research and
will be reported separately.
                                     -23-

-------
                                  FOOTNOTES
     The term "option value"  has  also  been  used  in connection with a differ-


ent concept related to risk version  in an atemporal setting.  Major references


include Schmalensee [1972], Bohm  [1975], Graham  [1981], Bishop  [1982], Smith


[1983], and Freeman [1984].

    2
     Obviously, if the control  decision  itself generates  information, this


may alter the balance of the  argument.  If,  by not controlling  now, one gener-


ates potentially useful information  which can be exploited  in future decisions


(for example, because the major uncertainty concerns  the  consequences of not


controlling), this would weaken the  case for control.   If,  on the other hand,


one generates useful information  by  controlling  now (because the major uncer-


tainty concerns the consequences  of  control), this would  strengthen the case


for control.  In the absence  of a specific  case  study,  it is difficult to say


a priori whether or not there is  dependent  learning and,  if there is, which


form it takes.  For this reason we have  focused  on the  case of  independent


learning.  For a further discussion  of this issue see Fisher and Hanemann


[1985].
                                     -24-

-------
                                  REFERENCES





Kenneth J. Arrow and Anthony C.  Fisher,  "Environmental preservation, uncer-



    tainty, and irreversibility," Quart. J.  Econ.  88, 312-319 (May 1974).



Kenneth J. Arrow and R.  C.  Lind, "Uncertainty and the evaluation of public



    investment decisions,"  Amer. Econ.  Rev.   60, 364-378 (1970).



R. C. Bishop, "Option value:  An exposition and extension," Land Econ.  58,



    1-15 (February 1982).



Peter Bohm, "Option demand  and consumer's surplus:  Comment," Amer. Econ.



    Rev.  65_, 733-736 (September 1975).



Larry G. Epstein, "Decision making and the temporal resolution of uncer-



    tainty," Inter_._Jcon_._^ev.  21, 269-283 (1980).



Anthony C. Fisher and W. Michael Hanemann, "Quasi-option value:  Some



    misconceptions dispelled," J. Environ. Econ. Manag. (forthcoming).



A. Myrick Freeman, "The size and sign of option value," Land Econ.  60, 1-13



    (February 1984).



D. A. Graham, "Cost-benefit analysis under uncertainty," Amer. Econ. Rev.  71,



    715-725 (September 1981).



Claude Henry, "Investment decisions under uncertainty:  The irreversibility



    effect," Amer. Econ. Rev.  64, 1006-1012 (December 1974).



A. J. Home, "A Suite of Indicator Variables (SIV) Index for an Aquatic



    Ecosystem," Energy and Resources Group, University of California, Berkeley



    (August 1985).



A. J. Home, J. Harte, and D. F. Von Hippel, "Predicting the Recovery of



    Damaged Aquatic Ecosystems:  A Hysteresis Trophic Link Model (HTLM),"



    Energy and Resources Group, University of California, Berkeley (August



    1985).
                                     -25-

-------
J. V. Krutilla and A.  C.  Fisher,  The Economics of National Environments:



    Studies in the Valuation of Commodity and Amenity Resources, Johns Hopkins



    Press, Baltimore (1975).



P. A. Samuelson, "Discussion," Amer. Econ. Rev.  M.,  93-96 (1964).



Richard Schmalensee, "Option demand and consumer's surplus:  Valuing price



    changes under uncertainty," Amer. Econ.  Rev.   62, 813-824 (December 1972).



V. Kerry Smith, "Option value:  A conceptual overview," Southern Econ. J.



    654-668 (January 1983).
                                     -26-

-------
                                       Page 1






     CHAPTER 6  THE  ECONOMIC CONCEPT OF BENEFIT





                                    INTRODUCTION






        Consider the question: "v/hat is the value of the wetlands of San




 Francisco Bay?".  V/hy might such a question be addressed to an economist rather




 than a philosopher or 3 poet?  To explain this it is vital to distinguish




 between tv/o  different meanings that might be attached to the original question:




 (i) Hew much value do people place on the wet lands  (assuming an adequate base of




 information)?   (ii) How much value ought they to place on them?  The  latter




 question  is  certainly the province of the philosopher or the poet; the economist




 too may have some thoughts about the question, but  these arise from his private




 sentiments,  not from  his professional discipline.   The former question - the




 positive  question -  is the one that the discipline  of economics addresses.  When




 we talk of benefits and benefit measurement in this report, we have this




- interpretation  in mind - the values that people actually place on ecosystems.




        This itself raises a host of questions: Which people?   In what units




 should values  be measured?  Why do people have these values?  Just how do we




 ascertain them? We will comment briefly on each of the  first three questions.




 The answers  to the fourth question will take up the remainder of this chapter,




 as well as Chapter 7.  Which people?  This  is specified,  in principle, by the




 agency commissioning  the benefit assessment.  A related, and more complex




 question,  is:  How do  we add up different people's values?  Again, this  is




 specified,  in  principle, by the agency commissioning the study; however, here




 there  is  a body of economic theory which can guide  the answer - see,  for




 example,  Sen (1973),  Blackorby and Donaldson  (1973), and Bcadway and  Sruce




 (1984, Chapter 9).   To save space, we will  duck this  issue here.  V/hat units?




 Values can be  measured  in monetary units or  in units of  any commodity that




 people happen  to value.  For example, we could measure the value to an

-------
                                       Pago  2






individual  of aquatic ecosystems  in  unite-  of chocolate truffles - Lake Tahoo is




worth 100 truffles,  say,  while Mono  Lake  is  worth  only 82 truffles.  Different




systems cf units will generate the ssnie ordinal  ranking of ecosystems, but not




necessarily the same cardinal  index  of  value.   We  choose to adopt noney -




purchasing power - as our unit of measurement  because this is the predominant




convention.  It is possible to develop  an  analogous theory of benefit




measurement based on chocolate truffle  units,  but  we shall not explore this




here (aggregation across individuals would presumably be more difficult).




        How do wo ascertain values?   In principle  there are two ways to proceed:




(i) Ask people directly, and  (ii) Rely  on  revealed preference - observe their




behavior when they make choices on which  the aquatic ecosystem somehow impinges,




and  infer their values from this behavior.  In this chapter we focus on the




latter approach exclusively.  An  immediate  implication  is an answer to the




question: Why do people have these values?  The answer  is that it  doesn't




matter.  V/e rely on  preferences as revealed by actual behavior, without needing




to know how these prefences might be decomposed into alternative motives.  Or




rather, there are two circumstances  in which motives might matter.  The first




is when a knowledge  of motives gives us reason to believe that preferences  (and




behavior) will be different in the future.  Stability of  preferences  is




essential to extrapolation from observed behavior.   If  preferences are not




stable, this poses both a philosophical and a practical  problem.   The




philosophical problem  is: Which set  of preferences do we rely on?  The practical




problem  is:  How can  we predict what  the new preferences will be  if it is




decided to rely on them?  The other  circumstance  in  which we might care about




motives  has  to  do with aggregation across individuals:  specifically,  a knowledge




of motives may  help  us to  identify groups of  individuals who have  different



preferences.  For empirical purposes,  it might bo more  appropriate to analyze




the  behavior of each group separately, rather than to aggregate  them  into a

-------
                                       Page 3






single group.




        Given  the focus oft revealed  preference,  why is the presence of markets




required for the success of our endeavor?   One answer common among non-




econor.tists,  but erroneous,  is that values  are  embodied in market prices and




expenditures.   Markets are needc-d because  market prices establish values: if a




commodity sells for 510, that is the value of  the commodity,  i-icv/over, this is




not exactly true.  If I buy the commodity  at a price of S10, then it certainly




must be worth 510 to me - but it may be worth  even more; i.e., the price is a




lower bound en value.   If I do not buy the commodity at this price, it is not




worth $10 to rna; i.e., the price is an upper bound.  Let us switch from prices




to expenditures and focus on the first case.  Suppose  I buy 5 units of the




commodity at the going price of $10, so that my total expenditure is 550.  This




expenditure is clearly a lower bound on the value of the commodity to me.  The




problem, however,  is that this  lower bound may be  inadequate for our purposes.




Ultimately we are  interested in net benefits - i.e. benefits minus costs.   If




the cost of supplying the commodity is also 310 a unit, the cost amounts to




S50 and the difference between that and our lower bound estimate of benefits  is




zero - because we  underestimate benefits when we use expenditures, we




underestimate net  benefits, possibly to the point of absurdity.  Moreover,




consider some change  in the supply of the commodity  (for example an improvement




in  its quality) which  leads me to spend $70 on it.  For the same reason as




before, this $70 is a  lower bound on the value of the  improved commodity to me.




But the change In  expenditure conveys absolutely no  information about the




channo  m vaIue; the difference between two lower bounds  is not necessarily a




lower bound on the difference  in the quantities being  bounded.




         In short,  we do not care about markets because market expenditures




directly indicate  values.  At best they provide bounds on values, but these




bounds are frequently so  imprecise as to be useless, and the channos  in market

-------
                                       Page 4






expenditures provide no information about changes in values.  Instead, wo cara




about markets because they provide a forurn for choice behavior - perform inn




tradeoffs between goods and money - from which v/e can indirectly infer




preferences.  That is the essence of the revealed preference approach.




iloracvar, as will be shov;n in the next section, these market transactions, or




tradeoffs, can convey information about preferences for other items of value




which are not themselves traded in a market, as  long as the preferences for the




latter items interact (in a sense to be made specific below) with preferences




for the traded items.  V/e turn, now, to an elaboration of this argument.








                             THE 3ASIC FRAMEWORK








        The revealed preference approach to benefit assessment can be explained




in terms of two basic consumer choice models.  Both models pertain to an




individual consumer - we want to avoid the complications associated with




estimation and interpretation of aggregate demand functions.  In the first




model, the  individual has preferences for various marketed commodities, whose




consumption  is denoted by the vector x, and for  various environmental resources,




which are denoted by q: this could be a vector but, for simplicity of notation,




we treat  it as a scalar.  These preferences are  represented by a utility




function u(x,q) which  is continuous and non-decreasing  in al! arguments (we




assume that the x's and q are all "goods"), and  strictly quasiconcave in x




(we assume  strict quasiconcavity rather than quasiconcavity  in order to rule




out demand correspondences).  At this point, we  do  not .assume that u( )  is




(strictly)  quasiconcave  in q.  The  individual chooses his consumption of the




marketed goods - the x's - by maximizing his utility subject to a budget



constraint

-------
                              page  5


where "the p.  "s are the prices of the marketed goods,  and  y  is  the
           i
individual's income.  Note that he  does not determine the level
of the q variables.  These are in the nature of public goods for
him, and he takes them as given.


     The utility maximization generates a pattern  of  consumption
behavior represented by the ordinary demand functions x.=hv(p,
q,y) i=l,...,N.  For convenience we assume that these represent
an interior solution, so that problems associated  with corner
solutions (discussed in Bockstael,  Hanemann, and Strand [1984,
Chapter 9] can be ignored.  Substitution of these  demand
functions into the direct utility function yields  the indirect
utility function v(p, q,y )su[h(p,q,y ) , q] .  Alternatively,  as a
dual to (1) there is an expenditure minimization problem
                        C.K  VA(X')SU.   X>0                (2)
which yields a set of compensated demand functions,  x.  =
                                                      i*
gMp^q/u), and the expenditure function m(p,q,u)  = £"p. gi (p, q, u) .


     These constructs can be employed to define what we mean  by
the benefits to the individual from a change in q.   Suppose that
q changes from q° to q1 ,  while prices and income  remain constant
a"t (p,y).  Accordingly, the individual's welfare  changes  from u°2
v(p,qe>,y) to u'= v(p,q' ,y).  Two alternative measures of this

-------
                              page 6








welfare change are the quantities C and E defined, respectively,



by
Each of these represents an adjustment to the individual's income



calculated to offset the effects of the change in q.  C, the



compensating variation, is the amount of money by which the



individual's income must be adjusted after the change in order to



render him as well off as he was before the change.  If u1 -C u° ,



so that C <. 0, this is the minimum compensation that he would



require in order to acquiesce in the change.  Similarly, E, the



equivalent variation, is the amount of money by which the



individual's income must be adjusted before the change in order



to render him as well off as he would be after it.  If u1 > u° ,



so that E > 0, this is the minimum compensation that he would



require in order to forego the change while, if u1 < u° so that E



< 0, this is the most he would be willing to pay to avoid the



change .








     The second model is based on the household production



approach,  in which the individual gains utility from "composite



commodities" which he produces himself from private goods.  One

-------
                              page 7
version of this model is
                uJxZ-}   s.K
where z denotes the vector of composite goods, f ( . ) is the
production function for these goods written in implicit form, and
w( . ) is a utility function defined over the z's and, perhaps,
some of the x's. In this formulation we are assuming that the
individual derives utility from q not directly, but indirectly,
in so far as they contribute to the production of z's.  The
utility maximization in (5) can be solved in two stages.  In the
first stage one obtains
                    =:  "^  ^(^^  s.K  Hx^^ =0,        (6)
while in the second stage one solves (1) using the function
u(x,q) derived from (6).  That is to say, a household production
model can always be "collapsed" into a model in the form given in
(1).  Moreover, welfare measures for changes in q can be defined
as in (3) and (4) using the indirect utility function v(p,q,y)
associated with u(x,q) in (6).  One consequence of the household
production approach, however, is that it generates demand (and
supply) curves for the z's - as well as demand curves for the x's
- which are of some empirical as well as theoretical interest.

     Given this framework,  our analysis will be concerned with
three sets of issues that have arisen in the literature on
environmental benefit evaluation;  (i) What is the relation
between C and E - we know they must have the same sign,  but how

-------
                              page 8




much can they differ in magnitude? (ii) How can we measure  C  and


E from observed demand behavior - after all, since we  do  not


observe utility directly we cannot estimate the indirect  utility


function v(p,q,y) directly?  (iii) Is there any relation  between


C or E and expenditures on some of the private goods - the  x's  -


which might be specially related to the q's in terms of either


consumer preferences or household production technology?  Can we


use expenditure on some goods as proxies for C or E?




     To answer these questions, it is convenient to consider


three possible markets.  One is the market for x's, in which


there are observable demand curves.  The second is the market for


z's, which may arise in connection with the household production


model (5).  The third market is entirely hypothetical.  Suppose


that the individual could actually buy q in a market at some


given price,TT . instead of (1) he would now solve


           mcv*   xxlx fl^  s.V.  ^OX.JT rto  r u                (7)
            X a                    " «••    V   .J

(at this point we assume strict quasiconcavity of u(.) with


respect to q in order to ensure an interior solution). Denote the


resulting ordinary demand functions for the x's by hu  (p,TT,y),

                                          A q
and the ordinary demand function for q by h ^ (p,tT, y).  The

                                                   >
associated indirect utility function is denoted by v (p,fT,y)s

  A          A 6.
u[h(p,rt,y), h/(p,IT,y)]. Similarly, we could define a dual


expenditure minimization problem analogous to (2), in which both


the x's and q are the choice variables.  The resulting

-------
                             page  9




                                            /*   __         A     _
compensated demand functions are denoted by g(p,n,u)  and gq(p,"


,u), and the expenditure function  is >* (p, fT,u.^ = £. P^fciT.wV fg^fp.iT,


     These utility maximization and expenditure minimization


problems are hypothetical because, in  fact, environmental


quality, q, is not a marketed commodity.  Nevertheless,  they are


of theoretical interest because they shed light on the solutions


to (1), (2), (5), and (6).  For example, it is convenient to


introduce the following:

                                        7 v       f    \
DEFINITION:  q is normal (inferior) if  hu  >O  ( G. ^





Moreover,

                    A V
PROPOSITION 2:   If V\ --O for all the q's which  change,  C = E.
                      J




Suppose, however, that there are income effects in the demand


functions for q;  the question remains: just how much  can C  and E


differ?  To answer this, we must investigate the q-market in more


detail.

-------
                             page  10
                   HOW  MUCH  CAN  C AND  E DIFFER?




     Willig (1976) established that, unless the income elasticity



of demand for a commodity is very high,  the compensating and




equivalent variations for a price change will not differ




considerably.  Some environmental economists do not believe that



the same holds true of compensating and equivalent variations for




change in q - see, for example,  Maler (1985, p.39) or Knetsch and



Sinden (1984), who ...-(present empirical evidence of a considerable



disparity between C and E. However, Randall and Stoll (1980) have



shown that Willig's analysis carries over to changes in fixed



parameters such as the q's,  and Brookshire, Randall and Stoll



(1980) have interpreted this result as implying that C and E



should not be very different in value.  How can these divergent



views be explained or reconciled?








     In the paper reproduced in the Appendix to this chapter I




reexamine randall and Stoll's analysis and show that,  while it is



indeed accurate,  its implications have been misunderstood.   There



is no presumption that C and E must be close in value and,  unlike



price changes, the difference between them depends not only on an



income effect but also on a  substitution effect.   Specifically,



the magnitude of  the difference  depends  on (i)  the magnitude of



the change in q,  (ii) the size of the income effects,  and (iii)



the degree of substitutability between private  consumption

-------
                             page 11





activities (the x's) and the level of environmental quality q in


the individual's preferences, all of which are empirical issues.


Moreover, I suggest that the substitution effects are likely to


exert far greater leverage, in practice, on the relation between


C and E than the income effects.  Thus, large empirical


divergences between C and E may be indicative not of some failure


in the survey methodology but of a general perception on the part


of the individuals surveyed that the private market goods


available in their choice set are, collectively, a rather


imperfect substitute for the public good under consideration.





               MEASURING C AND  E FROM DEMAND  CURVES


     Analysis of the market for q is useful in that it gives us


an idea of the factors that affect the relation between C and E,


but it is of no value when it comes to measuring C or E in


practice because, by definition, no such market exists - the


demand curve for q can never be observed.  What can be observed


is behavior in the x market - the market for private goods.  This


raises the question, therefore, of whether the values of C and E


can be inferred from knowledge of the demand curves from the x's.


There are two ways in which this can be accomplished.    The first

                 in
is to uncover the /direct utility function from the fitted demand


curves for the x's,  and then employ the formulas in (3) and (4).


The second is based upon results developed by Maler (1971,  1974)


which establish a relation between areas under demand curves for

-------
                             page   12

the x's and the quantities C and E.

     In the first approach one postulates  a  specific functional
form for either the direct utility  function  u(x,q)  or the
indirect utility function v(p,g,y),  and  derives  the appropriate
formula for the corresponding ordinary demand functions - by
analytically solving the direct utility  maximization problem or
by differentiating the indirect utility  function and applying
Roy's Identity.  Alternatively, one  can  start out with a given
system of ordinary demand functions  hf* (p,q,y) i.*\}-.,tJt  and then
attempt to recover the corresponding indirect utility function by
applying the integrability techniques developed  by  Hurwicz and
Uzawa.  As a simple example, suppose that  N=2 and the demand
function for the first good takes the semi-log form
           «M-X( , of- $(>,/£) + Y(«j/Pj * £^ ;                  (8)
in Hanemann (1980a, 1981) it is shown that the indirect utility
function is
            "
-------
                             page  13

E one first fits the demand function (8) and then substitutes the
estimated values of the coefficients ^ (?, f and  o  into the
formulas in (10a,b).

     The alternative approach to computing C and E-  developed by
Maler, is based on the following decomposition of the formula for
C (a similar analysis applies to E)
     c - ^- ^fp-V,^
                                                    <£t,V) - Airp.^.oO J
where p is an arbitrary price vector.  Assuming that q1 > q° , we
know that C > 0.  Since mq£. 0, we also know that the second term
in (11) is non-negative.  The first term is the sum of areas
between compensated demand curves corresponding to q1 and q° ,
                                      tPi            *••*
between the actual price p±  and the i  element of p (this line
integral is path-independent).  It should be emphasized that the
first item is not necessarily positive;  it can be shown that the
increase in q raises the compensated demand for the i* h private
good (^gi/3q>0) if this good is a complement to q in the Hicks-
Allen sense,  and lowers the compensated demand (^gi/Sq<0) if the
good is a substitute.  Moreover, if q is a scalar,  at least one
of the private goods must be a Hicks-Allen substitute for q.
Nevertheless,  we know that the sum of the two terms in (8) must
          P
       =  \    Lf.,oO-fvO]d. t  ^(,^0-™.0)      00

-------
                             page  14






be positive.






     Maler's trick is to select p in such a way  that  the  second


term in (| [) vanishes.  For this purpose, he introduces  two



assumptions.  The novel assumption is that there exists a set  of



commodities with the property that, if these commodities  are not


being consumed, the marginal utility of q is zero.  Let I be the


index set of these commodities, and I its complement.   Partition


the vector x accordingly: x = (x  'X7 )•  Maler's assumption,


which he calls weak complementarity, is:






(WC)  There exists a non-empty set I such that    <3_^( Q*?'^'  — &


                                                  H         (12)






His second assumption is:


(NE) The commodities in I are non-essential:  there exists  some


price vector such that g1 ( . ) = 0 and hi(.) = 0 all i e. I.






We can now apply these assumptions to (11) by choosing  the  price

       s^         *V              *""                  ***
vector p so that p± = p.^ for i E. I while, for it.  I, p± is  simply



the cut-off price of the i* h  compensated demand function - i.e.



                           }]* ^'  SillCe S±9n (mq)= - S±9n  
-------
                             page 15
     This proposition establishes a relationship between C and



the areas between two sets of compensated demand functions.  It



is useful here to make a distinction between two sets of



circumstances:  (i) there is a set of goods with the property



that q has no value only when none of these goods is being



consumed, and (ii) there is a set of goods with the property that



q has no value when any one of them is not being consumed.  In



the first case,  C is measured by the area between compensated



demand curves summed over all of the goods in I; in the second



case it is measured by the area between compensated demand curves



for any one of the goods in I,  and we obtain the same answer



regardless of the particular good selected.   Note that,  in order



to make use of the proposition,  one still needs to know something



more than ordinary demand functions unless there are no income



effects in the demand for the goods in I, in which case the



compensated and ordinary demand functions coincide.   If there are



income effects and one attempts to calculate the area in ( 13 )



using ordinary instead of compensated demand functions,  i.e. one



calculates the area
this is likely to be of limited value.   The issue is examined in



Hanemann (1980b), where it is shown that under some circumstances



S may not even have the correct sign.   The requirement that one



employ the compensated demand function in (13) implies that,

-------
                             page 16

wherever there are income effects,  Maler's method for calculating
C and E has the same information requirements as the method based
on direct application of (3)  and (4).   Finally,  as an
illustration, it turns out that semi-log demand function (8)
satisfies the WC condition since, on differentiating the indirect
utility function (9), one finds that
                u
which is equivalent to (12).   The compensated demand function
corresponding to (13)  is
          *^YP,*?,^ . Mi-  ^- e.^Pi/p^~  ^  1
           1  J  ' *  J   y L    vA            J
and it is straightforward to  verify that (lOa)  and (lOb) combine
to satisfy (13).
                THE LIMITS TO REVEALED PREFERENCE
     Both of the methods for measuring C and E from observed
demand functions rely on the assumption that all  the relevant
components of the indirect utility function can be recovered from
demand functions.  However,  that assumption is not always true:
it holds when the underlying direct utility function has the form
               u = u(x, ^}                                    (17)
as has implicitly assumed up to now,  but not when the utility
function can be cast into the form

-------
                             page  17
                                                             <18>
where T( . ) is increasing in its first argument and u(x,q) is a


conventional direct utility function.  It can be shown that both


utility models imply exactly the same ordinary demand functions


for x's

           C.TO mox  U (x( ^) r arg. mw  T L ^ ( *, ^\ <^ J
             
-------
                             page 18

where C satisfies v(p,q1,y-C) = v(p,q°,y), v( . ) being the
indirect utility function corresponding to~u(x,q), and C*
satisfies
                                                             (20)
Assuming that q1 > q° and T(.,q) is increasing in q, it can be
shown that C* > 0, so that
                            C >  C? >  0.                       (21)

A similar result can be shown to hold for equivalent variation
measures:
                        E  =  E? +  E*>  E  >  0,                   (22)
where E is the true equivalent variation associated with the full
utility function u(x,q) in (18), E is the equivalent variation
associated with the sub-function u(x,q), and E* is calculated
from the transformation function T(.,q), along the lines of (20).
Since C and E are derived from the sub-function containing the
interactions between the x's and q, we can regard them as the
"consumption - or use - related" components of benefits.
Similarly,  we can regard C*  and E*  as the "non-consumption
related" or "non-use related" components of benefits - they arise
from that part of the individual's preferences which do not
affect his choice of x.

-------
                             page  19
     The practical implications of (18) for the revealed

preference approach - the measurement of C and E on the basis of

observed demands for the x's - are highly important. If we only

have data on ordinary demand functions for the x's, we can only

recover u(x,q), but never T(.,q) nor the full utility function

u(x,q) in (18).  That is, we can only measure C and E - not C* or

E* and, therefore, not the full value of C or E.  This is a

significant limitation to the revealed preference approach.



     It is sometimes thought that Maler's Weak Complementarity

(WC) assumption eliminates this problem, but I would dispute

this.  Differentiate (18) to obtain the marginal utility of q.
                                                            (23)
                act
If we apply WC to u(x,q), this requires that
                                                            (24)
But, by itself, this is not enough to ensure that
                        5  O,                               (25)
which is what one requires in order to rule out the

-------
                             page  20
representation in (18).  Suppose, for example, that





                                 fi  xr  -°
This satisfies (24) but not (25), and therefore C* > 0 and



E* > 0. In this case WC does not eliminate the problem.








     To summarize, the only circumstance in which the revealed



preference approach to the measurement of C and E is fully



satisfactory is when (25) holds - i.e. the utility function is



represented by (17) rather than (18).  But there is no way to



verify this from data on ordinary demand functions for x's.  It



could be verified if there were a market for q and one could



observe demand functions for q as well as the x's.  Indeed, in



that case, T(.,q) could be recovered along with u(x,q) so that,



if (25) were violated, C and E could still be calculated because



one would obtain the full indirect utility function associated



with (18).  But,  in the absence of a market for q, the problem



remains.








     In practice, there are two possible solutions.  The first is



simply to assume that the utility function takes the form of (17)



and not (18) - which is what is generally done. The second is to



collect additional behavioral data besides ordinary demand



functions for the x's.  For example,  after measuring C by the

-------
                             page 21






revealed preference approach one could conduct interviews to


elicit the willingness to pay for an improvement in q directly;


if the interviews yielded an estimate close to C in value one


would conclude that C* = 0 and hence, the utility model


corresponds to (17) rather than (18). If they yielded an estimate


much greater than C one would take the difference to be a measure


of C* .  Alternatively, instead of contingent valuation exercises,


one could conduct what has been called [Hanemann (1985)]


"contingent behavior" exercises in which one attempts to elicit a


hypothetical demand function for q.  Both of these approaches


remain subjects for future research.






               THE  SIGNIFICANCE OF EXPENDITURE DATA


     In the theory of the welfare measurement of price changes it


is well known that calculation of expenditure changes provide


bounds on the compensating and equivalent variations, even if


they are not exactly equal to these welfare measures.  If prices


change from p°  to p1 and the quantities demand change


correspondingly from x°  to x1 ,  then the compensating variation

                       ?                                 a
for the price change, C , and the equivalent variation,  E ,


satisfy
and
although,  in general,  there is no determinate relation between C

-------
                             page  22







or E and the overall change in expenditure  5p.x° -
     When dealing with changes in q, as opposed to price  changes,



some authors have wondered whether one can obtain a  relation



between the welfare measures C and E and the change  in



expenditures on some or all of the private market goods,  £. p \.W(p.G



 - V\"(PI«J/, jj} J •     In general, I do not believe that this is  a



useful approach; with one exception described below, there  does



not appear to be any determinate relation between changes in



expenditure on x's and either C and E. Indeed, the effect of an



increase in q on the demand function for any of the  x's is  by  no



means obvious.  Given that (Su/^q) > 0, it is sometimes assumed



that ^h1" /^q i. 0 all i  - an increase in quality can  never lower



the demand for any of the x's.  In fact, this is not true;  in



general, an increase in q will affect the demand for the  x's,  but



note that the effect could be in either direction, depending on



the specifics of the utility function.  Even if q is a Hicks-



Allen complement with some private good -say, x - it is not



necessarily true that an increase in q will raise the demand for



that good.







     This pessimistic conclusion is based on the following



proposition which links the demand functions x. = h>"(p,q,y) to
                                      A L
the hypothetical demand functions x = hl(p,(T,y) associated with



the utility maximization problem (7):

-------
                              page 23








PROPOSITION 4:  Let  fi~ =n (p,q,y)  be defined implicitly by



Appendix equation  (11).   Then,



                                                  • ,    ^      (27)
It follows as a corollary  that
                                                              (28)
                         U^/dr?
Given that uq > 0, /T  > 0.   If  u(x,q)  is quasiconcave in q, the



denominator of the second  term on the RHS is negative.  Thus, the



sign of 3hc /^q depends upon a  complex set of factors.  The



numerator of the term in braces on the RHS will be recognized as



the cross-price derivative of  the compensated demand curve from q
and this is positive or negative  according as x .  and q are



substitutes or complements.  Moreover,



          rtr^-l  .r  U) <-| - |   ^  O   CLS   nf?^"^"



where  _ qn. % Thus, if d^/jti >O    and
                            >o                              (29)
this is a sufficient condition  for  ^(rx^/c^s >0 . Even if ^W/ita^O, it

-------
                              page  24








 can still happen that ^ W^ "> 0 if (29) holds and that term is



 sufficiently large.








      Without belaboring it further, the point is that an increase



 in q could either lower or raise the expenditure on x.  This



 should make us cautious about expected any simple relation



 between the change in expenditure on some of the x ' s and C or E



 since it is quite possible that C and E are positive while the



 change in expenditure is negative.  One case in which more



 definitive results can be obtained is where q is a perfect



 substitute for some of the x's - say x.^ .  In that case the direct



 utility function takes the form
 where i|^ (.) is some increasing function of q.  Let h1(p,y) and



v(p,y) be the ordinary demand function for good 1 and the indirect



 utility function associated with u( . ) .   The following may be



 shown:








 PROPOSITION 5:  If u(x,q) has the form given in (30),
                                                             Ola)

-------
                             page 25
It follows from (31b) that
while the change in expenditure on x is
                                                            (32)
                   as
Thus, if X-L is a normal good and a perfect substitute for q, the

change in the expenditure on x1 understates the true benefit from

an increase in q. In this case, moreover, there are no income

effects in the demand curve for q, so that the compensating and

equivalent variations coincide.  Apart from this special case,

however, there does not appear to be any determinate relation

between A and C or E.




                          NON-USE  VALUES

     This above framework can be used to shed some light on the

concept of existence value due originally to Krutilla (1967).

This is based on the notion that,  even if he did not consume any

of the x's that are associated with q,  an individual might still

feel some improvement in q and be willing to pay something to

secure it.  How can this be explained in terms of the utility

model discussed above?

-------
                             page  26








     Smith and Desvousges (1986) have made an important



distinction between existence values under conditions of



certainty and uncertainty.  The phenomenon of consumer choices



under uncertainty -e.g. the individual does not know whether or



not he will want in the future to consume certain x's that are



associated with q - raises many important issues that transcend



the theory developed above,  which is firmly rooted in the context



of decisions under certainty.  Accordingly, I focus here on the



concept of existence values under the conditions of certainty -



an individual places some value on an improvement in q even



though he does not himself consume any of the x's that might be



associated with q, and has no doubt that he will never consume



these goods in the future.  Under these circumstances, how can we



use the theoretical framework developed above to give some



operational meaning to this concept?








     Two quantities identified above may have some bearing on



this question.  The first is based on the decomposition in (11).



Suppose that Weak Complementarity does not apply so that<)u/^q > 0



even when there is zero consumption of x's that are



conventionally associated with q.  In that case one could regard



the quantity
                                                            (33)

-------
                             page  27








as a measure of the non-use benefits associated with the



improvement in q - these are the benefits that would accrue to



the individual even if he were consuming none of the x ' s .



Operationally, one would measure them by computing C from the



indirect utility function using (3),  and then subtracting the



area between the compensated demand curves represented by the



integral on the RHS of (33).  of course, if Weak Complementarity



holds, this quantity is zero.  As already noted, that would apply



to the semi-log demand function (8).   Interestingly, it does not



apply to another common functional form, the linear ordinary



demand function
It can be shown that the corresponding compensated demand



function Q(p,q,u) is independent of q so that the integral in



(11) and (33) is zero and
                                                            (35)
where the cut-off price is
In this case,  therefore,  all of the benefit from a change in q is

-------
                             page 28








associated with term jWp',
-------
                             page 29








extreme form in (37), a similar conclusion would apply: "the only



way to measure the non-use benefits C* and E* is by contingent



valuation and/or contingent behavior procedures.

-------
                            REFERENCES


W. Michael Hanemann (1980a) "Measuring the Worth of Natural
Resource facilities: Comment" Land Economics Vol. 56  November
1980  pp. 482-486

W. Michael Hanemann (1980b) "Quality Changes, Consumer's Surplus
and Hedonic Price Indices," University of California, Department
of Agricultural and Resource Economics, Working paper No. 116,
Berkeley, November 1980.

W. Michael Hanemann (1981)  "Some Further Results on Exact
Consumer's Surplus"  University of California, Department of
Agricultural and Resource Economics, Working paper No. 190,
Berkeley, December, 1981.

W. Michael Hanemann (1985)  "Some Issues in Discrete - and
Continuous - Response Contingent Valuation Studies,"
Northeastern Journal of Agricultural Economics, April 1985

John V. Krutilla (1967) "Conservation Reconsidered," American
Economic Review Vol. 57, September 1967, pp 777-786

Karl-Goran Maler (1971), "A Method of Estimating Social Benefits
From Pollution Control,"  Swedish Journal of Economics  Vol. 73,
No. 1, pp 121-133

Karl-Goran Maler (1974), Environmental Economics: A Theoretical
Inquiry  (Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press)

V. Kerry Smith and William H. Desvousges (1986), Measuring Water
Quality Benefits (Boston: Kluwer-Nijhoff Publishing Co.)

-------
                                 APPENDIX



   WILLINGNESS TO PAY AND WILLINGNESS TO ACCEPT:  HOW MUCH CAN THEY DIFFER?






    Consider an improvement  in the  exogenous variables comprising an indi-



vidual's choice set.  Two possible  monetary measures  of the gain  in her wel-



fare are the compensating variation (C)  and the equivalent variation (E).  In



the present context, these correspond, respectively,  to the maximum amount the



individual would be willing  to pay  (WTP) to secure  the change and the minimum



compensation that she would  be willing to  accept  (WTA) to  forego  the change.



How much can the two differ,  and what are  the  factors that determine the dif-



ference?  These Questions were addressed by Robert  Willig  (1976)  in his path-



breaking paper on the welfare measurement  of price  changes.  Willig argued



that C and E are likely in practice to be  fairly  close in  value, and he showed



that the difference depends  directly on  the size  of the income elasticity of



demand for the commodity whose price changes.



    In many empirical studies, however,  analysts  seek to obtain money measures



of welfare changes due not to price changes but to  changes in the availability



of public goods or amenities,  changes in the qualities of  commodities, or



changes in the fixed quantities of  rationed goods.  Karl-Goran Maler (1974)



was perhaps the first to show that  the concepts of  C  and E can readily be ex-



tended from conventional price changes to  quantity  changes such as these.



Subsequently,  Alan Randall and John Stoll  (1980)  examined  the duality theory



associated with fixed quantities in the  utility function and showed that, with



appropriate modifications, Willig's formulas for  bounds on C and E do, indeed,



carry over to this setting.   Within the  environmental  literature and else-



where,  Randall and Stoll's results  have  been widely interpreted as implying



that WTP and WTA for changes  in environmental  amenities should not differ

-------
                                     -2-






greatly unless there  are unusual income effects.   However, recent empirical



work using various types of  interview procedures has produced some evidence of



large disparities between WTP and OTA measures--for example, Richard C. Bishop



and Thomas A. Hebertein (1979)  and  several  studies described by Irene M.



Gordon and Jack L. Knetsch (1979),  and by Knetsch and Sinden (1984).  This has



led to something of an impasse:  How can the empirical evidence of significant



differences between WTP and  OTA be  reconciled with the theoretical analysis



suggesting that such differences are unlikely?  Can they be explained entirely



by unusual income effects or by peculiarities of the interview process?




    In this note I reexamine Randall and Stoll's analysis and show that, while



it is indeed accurate, its implications have been misunderstood.  For quantity



changes there is no presumption that OTP and OTA must be close in value and,



unlike price changes, the difference between OTP and OTA depends not only on



an income effect but  also on a  substitution effect.  By the latter, I mean the



ease with which other privately marketed commodities can be substituted for



the given public good or fixed  commodity, while maintaining the individual at



a constant level of utility. I show that,  holding income effects constant,



the smaller the substitution effect (i.e.,  the fewer substitutes available for



the public good) the  greater the disparity  between OTP and OTA.  This surely



coincides with common intuition.  If there  are private goods which are readily



substitutable for the public good,  there ought to be little difference between



an individual's OTP and OTA  for a change in the public good.  But, if the pub-



lic good has almost no substitutes  (e.g., Yosemite National Park or, in a dif-



ferent context, your  own life), there is no reason why OTP and OTA could not



differ vastly—in the limit, OTP could equal the individual's entire (finite)




income while OTA could be infinite.  My argument is developed in the following

-------
                                     -3-
two sections.   Section  I deals specifically with the two polar cases of per-

fect substitution and zero  substitution between the public good and available

private goods.   Section II  deals with Randall and Stoll's extension of

Willig's formulas and shows that their bounds are, in fact, consistent with

substantial divergences between WTP and WTA.


                             I.  Two Polar Cases


    The theoretical setup is as follows.  An individual has preferences for

various conventional market commodities whose consumption is denoted by the

vector x as well as for another commodity whose consumption is denoted by

q.   This could represent the  supply of a public good or amenity; it could

be an index of the quality  of  one of the private goods; or it could be a

private commodity whose consumption is fixed by a public agency.   The key

point is that the individual's consumption of q is fixed exogenously, while

she can freely vary her consumption of the x's.  These preferences are repre-

sented by a utility function,  u(x, q), which is continuous and nondecreasing

in its arguments (I assume  that the x's and q are all "goods") and strictly

quasiconcave in x.  The individual chooses her consumption by solving


(1)                    max  u(x, q) subject to £pjX- = y
                       x


taking the level of q as given.  This yields a set of ordinary demand func-

tions, x-  = h1(p, q, y), i  = 1,  ..., N, and an indirect utility function,

v(p, q, y) E u[h(p, q,  y),  q], which has the conventional properties with

respect to the price and income arguments and also is increasing in q.   Now

suppose that q rises from a to q  > q  while prices and income remain constant

-------
                                     -4-






at (p, y) .   Accordingly, the individual's utility changes from u  = v(p, q ,  y)



to u  = v(p, q ,  y)  >  u .  Following Nfaler, the compensating and equivalent



variation measures of  this change are defined, respectively, by






(2)                       v(p, q1, y - C) = v(p, q°, y)







(3)                      v(p, q1, y) = v(p, q°, y + E) .






Dual to the utility  maximization in (1)  is an expenditure minimization:  Mini-



mize £p-x-  with respect to x subject to u = u(x, q), which yields a set of



compensated demand functions, x. = g1(p, q, u), i = 1,  — , N, and an expendi-



ture function, m(p,  q, u) = Zp-g1(p, q, u), which has the conventional proper-



ties with respect to (p, u) and is decreasing in q.  In terms of this function,



C and E are given by






(2')                     C = m(p, q°, u°) - m(p, q1, u°)







(31)                     E = m(p, q°, u1) - m(p, q1, u1) -





    It is evident from (2) and (3) that 0 <_ C _< y while E >_0.   The questions



at issue are:  (1) Is  it true that E/C « 1?  (2) What factors affect this



ratio?  As  a first cut at an answer, I compare two polar cases.  In the first



case at least one private good--say, the first—is a perfect substitute for



some transformation  of q.  Thus, the direct utility function assumes the



special form
(4)                     u(x, q) = U[

-------
                                     -5-
where \jj(-) is an increasing function and u(«)  is  a continuous, increasing,

strictly quasiconcave function of N variables.  As W. M. Gorman  (1976) has

shown, the resulting indirect  utility  function  is
(5)
    , q, y) =
where v(«) is the indirect utility function corresponding to u(').  Substi-

tution of (5) into (2) and (3)  yields  the  following:


PROPOSITION 1:  If at least one private market  good  is a perfect substitute

for q, then C = E.


    At the opposite extreme, I  assume  that there is  a zero elasticity of sub-

stitution not just between q and x-,  but between q and ajJ. the x's.  Thus,

the direct utility function becomes
(6)
u(x, q) = u
mm ( q, — ] , ..., mm [ q.
        al
where a-,, ..., a^ are positive constants and u(«)  is a conventional direct

utility function.  In this case the indirect utility function v(p, q, y) has a

rather complex structure and  changes its form  in different segments of (p, q, y)

space.  It will be sufficient for  my purposes  to focus on just one of these seg-

ments.  Suppose that q <_y/Zp.  a-;  then the maximization of (6), subject to the

budget constraint, yields ordinary demand  functions and an indirect utility func-

tion of the form x^^ = h1(p, q,  y)  = c^ q,  and  u =  v(p, q, y) = u~(q, ..., q) =

w(q).  In this region of (p,  q, y)  space,  the  individual does not exhaust her

-------
                                     -6-
budget, and her marginal  utility of  income is therefore zero.  Now suppose that

q  £y/Zp-a- and q  > q  .   Since v(p, q  , y) > w(q  ), it is evident from (2)

that the individual would be willing to  pay some positive but limited amount C

to secure this change. However, for any positive quantity E, no matter how

large, v(p, q , y + E) =  v(p,  q  , y) = w(q ).  This implies the following:



PROPOSITION 2:  If there  is zero substitutability between q and each of the

private market goods, it  can happen  that, while the individual would only be

willing to pay a finite amount for an increase  in q, there is no finite com-

pensation that she would  accept to forego this increase.


    It should be emphasized that this result obtains only in a portion of
                                                                   Q
Cp> Q> y) space; in other regions, even  with (6), E would be finite.   How-

ever, the result in Proposition 2 can also be established for other utility

functions that permit some substitutability between q and the x's as long as

the indifference curves between q and each of the x's become parallel to the

q axis at some point. The lesson to be  learned from these two propositions is

that the degree of substitutability  between q and private market goods signifi-

cantly affects the relation between  C and E.  In the next section, I show how

this observation can be reconciled with  the bounds on C and E derived by

Randall and Stoll.


                       II.  Randall and Stoll's Bounds



    In order to extend Willig's bounds from price to commodity space, Randall

and Stoll focus on a set  of demand functions different from those considered

above.  Suppose that the  individual  could purchase q in a market at some given

-------
                                     -7-



price, TT.  It must be emphasized that this  market is entirely hypothetical
                                                                       g
since q is actually a public good.   Instead of (1),  she would now solve



(7)                   max u(x,  q) subject to Zp-x^ + irq = y.
                      x,q


                                                       s\ -I
Denote the resulting ordinary demand functions by x- = h (p,  TT,  y),  i  = 1,

..., N and q = hq(p, IT,  y).   The corresponding indirect utility function is

v(p, TT, y) = u[h(p, TT, y), hq(p, TT,  y)].   The dual to (7) is:  Minimize

Zp.x. + Trq with respect to x and q  subject to u = u(x, q).  This generates

a set of compensated demand functions,  x- = gHp, TT, u), i =  1,  ..., N and

q = gq(p, TT, u), and an expenditure function, m(p, TT, u) = Zp-g^p,  TT, u) +

Trg^tp, TT, u).  These functions  are hypothetical since q is really exogenous to


the individual, but they are of theoretical interest because they shed light

on the relation between C and E.

    For any given values of q,  p, and u,  the equation,



(8)                               q = gq(p, TT, u^


may be solved to obtain TT = nCp, q,  u), the inverse compensated demand (i.e.,

willingness to pay) function for q:   9(0 is the price that would induce the

individual to purchase q units  of the public good in order to attain a utility

level of u, given that she could buy private goods at prices  p.   Let TT  =

Ti(p, q , u ) and TT  = n(p, q ,  u )  denote the prices that would have supported

q  and q , respectively.  The two expenditure functions dual  to (1)  and (7) are

related by:



(9)              m(p, a, u)  E m[p,  Ti(p, q,  u), u] -  Ti(p, q, u) • q.

-------
                                     -8-





This implies that*0






(10)                       mq(p, q, u)  =  -ir(p, q, u) .






Combining (10) with (2') and  (31) yields these alternative  formulas for C and



E expressed in terms of the willingness -to -pay function:
(2")                           C =  / 0 irCp,  q,  uU)  dq

                                    q
(3")                           E = / Q n(p,  q,  u1)  dq .

                                    q



It can be shown that sign (TT )  = sign (h^) .  Therefore,  for given  (TT, q), the


         "        1                             "^        0
graph of Ti(p, q, u ) lies above (below) that of TT(P, q,  u ), and E >  (<) C,



accordingly as q is a normal (inferior) good.   Figure  1  shows E and C for the



case where q is normal:  E corresponds to the area  q   a  y q  while C corre-



sponds to the area q  3 6 q .



    Using the technique pioneered by Willig, Randall and Stoll establish



bounds on the difference between each of C and  E and the area under an inverse



ordinary demand function for q.  From this,  they derive  bounds on  the differ-



ence between C and E.  However, the requisite inverse  ordinary demand function



is obtained in a rather special manner.  Given  any  level of q, we  can ask what



market price TT would induce the individual to purchase that amount of public



good if it were available in a  market, while still  allowing her to purchase



the quantity of the x's that she actually did buy at market prices p with in-



come y.  In conducting this thought experiment, one needs to supplement her

-------
                  -9-
FIGURE J.   WTP and WTA for a  Change  in  q

-------
                                     -10-





income so that she can afford q as well as  the  x's.   Thus,  for given (p,  q,  y) ,



we seek the price IT that satisfies






(11)                           q = hq(p, TT,  y + TO) .



                                    /\

The solution will be denoted by IT =  irCp, q,  y).  This inverse function is



related to the inverse compensated demand function by the identities11






(12a)                     7i(p, q, y) = ir[p,  q,  v(p, q, y) ]






(12b)                     TT(P, q, u) = Tr[p,  q,  m(p, q, u)].




                            0   A     0   0    "^     0          1
It follows from (12a) that TI  = ir(p, q , u  ) =  ir(p, q , y)  and TT  =


~     1   1    A     1                         •*
rr(p, q , u ) = Tr(p, q , y)--i.e., the graph of  irCp, q, y) as a function of q



intersects the graph of TT(P, q, u )  at q =  q ,  and the graph of TT(P, q, u )  at


     1                                12
q = q .  This is depicted in Figure  1.

                                      /\

    Using the inverse demand function irCp,  q, y), define the quantity
(13)                           A = / Q TT(P,  q, y)  dq

                                    q




which corresponds to the area q  $ y <$ q  in Figure 1.  This is a sort of



Marshallian consumer's surplus, which is to  be compared with C and E.   Let
                                   31n rcC
be the income elasticity of Tr(p,  q,  y);  Randall  and Stoll call this the "price



flexibility of income."  Assume that,  over  the range from (p,  q ,  y) to



(p, q ,  y), this elasticity is  bounded from below by £  and from above by

-------
                                    -11-
£  with neither bound equal to 1.  Using the mean-value theorem, as in

Willig's equation (18),  and the above equations (21), (3'), (10), (12b), (13),


and (14), yields Randall and Stoll's result—namely,



PROPOSITION 3:  Assume £L  <_ £ <_ £U where £L £ 1 and £U £ 1.  Then,
  (i) 0 <
               (i - r) 9

 (ii) 0 < 1 -
                1  -  (1 -
                                  -u
(iii)  If £U <  1, or if £u > 1 and 1 + (1 -
1°' f 1
1 + (1 - 51
J, A
y
                                                                              - i
 (iv)  If C  >  1, or if C  < 1 and 1 - (1 -
                                              y ^ 0, ^ £ 1 -
1 - (1 -
-Ll A
'   y
Applying a Taylor approximation, as in Willig, and assuming that the condi-

tions in (iii) and (iv)  are satisfied, one obtains
(15)
    This is commonly interpreted as implying that C and E are close in value,


but whether or not that is correct clearly depends on the magnitudes of (A/y)


and the bounds f;  and E, .   The magnitude of (A/y) depends in part on the size


of the change from q  to q .  But what can be said about the likely magnitude

-------
                                     -12-
of the income elasticity,  £--could it happen, for example, that £L = °°?  To



answer that question, differentiate (11) implicity
(16)
                   37
                                   ,  TT, y + irq) + qhtp, TT, y + Trq)
By the Hicks-Slutsky decomposition, the denominator is equal to the own-price



derivative of the compensated demand function for q and is nonpositive
                             = h°(p, TT, y + Trq) + q h£(p, TT, y + Trq) <_ 0.
Converted to elasticity form, (16) becomes
(16')                              g = - n" a)
where n = (y + rrq) h^(p, rr, y + qir)/q is the income elasticity of the direct



ordinary demand function for q, a = qrr/(y + qir) is the budget share of q in re-



lation to "adjusted" income, and e = Trgq[p, TT, v(p, q, y)]/q is the own- price



elasticity of the compensated demand function for q.  The last term can be re-



lated to the overall elasticity of substitution between q and the private mar-



ket goods x^, ..., x^.  By adapting W. E. Diewert's (1974) analysis, it can be



shown that, if the prices p,, ___ , p^ vary in strict proportion (i.e., p. = e~p.



for some fixed vector p), the aggregate Allen-Uzawa elasticity of substitution



between q and the Hicksian composite commodity XQ E Zp-x., denoted OQ, is



related to the compensated own-price elasticity for q by the formula:  e =



-ov,(l - a).  Hence, (16') may be written

-------
                                     -13-
(16")
                                          C0
where OQ >_ 0 .

      This provides an explanation of  the  results  in the previous  section.  For

changes in q,  unlike changes  in p,  the extent of the difference between C and

E depends not only on income  effects  (i.e.,  n)  but also on  substitution ef-

fects (i.e., an).  If, over the relevant range, either n =  0  (no income ef-

fects) or an = co (perfect substitution between  q and one or more of the x's),

then E,  = £  = 0 and, from Proposition 3,  C  = A =  E. On the  other hand,

if the demand function for q  is highly income elastic, or there are very few

substitutes for q among the x's so that aQ is close to zero,  this  could

generate very large values of £ and substantial divergences between C and E.

Suppose, for example, that, over  the  relevant range, a lower  bound on the income
              ~        i
elasticity of TT(') is E,  = 20 (e.g.,  r\ = 2 and  aQ  = 0.1) and  A/y = 0.05.

Then, from Proposition 3 (i and iv), C/y <_ 0.0345  while 0.1708 <_ E/y, so that E

is at least five times larger than C.    Higher values of £  would imply even

greater differences between C and E.



                               III.  Conclusion



    A recent assessment of the state of the  art of public good valuation con-

cludes "Received theory establishes that . . . WTP .  . . should approximately

equal . . . OTA. ...  In contrast with theoretical axioms which  predict

small differences between WTP and WTA, results from contingent valuation

method applications wherein such  measures  are derived almost  always demon-

strate large differences between  average WTP and WTA.  To date, researchers

-------
                                     -14-
have been unable to explain  in any definitive way the persistently observed



differences between WTP and  WTA measures"  (Cummings, Brookshire, and Schulze,



p. 41).  This paper offers an explanation by showing that the theoretical



presumption of approximate equality  between WTP and WTA is misconceived.  This



is because, for public goods, the relation between the two welfare measures



depends on a substitution effect as  well as an income effect.  Given that the



substitution elasticity appears in the denominator of (16") and the Engel



aggregation condition places some limit on the plausible magnitude of the



numerator, this suggests that the substitution effects are likely to exert far



greater leverage, in practice, on the relation between WTP and WTA than the



income effects.  Thus, large empirical divergences between WTP and WTA may be



indicative not of some failure in the survey methodology but of a general



perception on the part of the individuals  surveyed that the private market



goods available in their choice set  are, collectively, a rather imperfect



substitute for the public good under consideration.

-------
                                     -15-



                                  FOOTNOTES



     This view is expressed by,  for example, Myrick Freeman  (1979, p. 3);


Mark A. Thayer (1981,  p.  30); Jack L. Knetsch and J. A. Sinden (1984, p. 508);


and Don L. Coursey, William D. Schulze, and John J. Hovis  (1984, p. 2).

    2
     I am treating q as a scalar here, but it could be a vector without


seriously affecting the analysis in this section.  In the next section, how-


ever, the analysis would become  significantly more complex if q were a vector


and more than one element of q changed.


     These alternative interpretations are offered, respectively, by Maler,


W. Michael Hanemann (1982), and  Randall and Stoll.

    4
     These properties are established in my earlier paper.


     I have taken the liberty of defining C and E as the negative of quan-


tities appearing in Willig and in Randall and Stoll, so that sign (C) =


sign (E) = sign (u  -  u ).


     I assume throughout that q  > q  and u  ^ u  .  The analysis could be


repeated for a case in which quality  decreases and u  £ u  .  In that case, C


and E are both nonpositive and correspond, respectively, to  the compensation


that the individual would be willing  to accept to consent to the change and


the amount that she would be willing  to pay to avoid the change.  This would


reverse the inequalities presented below, but it would not affect the sub-


stance of my argument.


     This result carries over, of course, if more than one private good is a


perfect substitute for q.  In the most general case, u(x, q) = u[x, + ^-.(q),


..., XN + v|»N(q)] and C = E = Ep^Cq1) - ^(q0)].

-------
                                     -16-




    Q           —:                          f\

     Indeed, if h (cup,, ...,  a.^ p^,  y)  <_ q ,  i = 1, ...,  N, it can be shown



that v(p, q , y) = v(p, q ,  y) = vta^,  ...,  «NPN, v)  and C = E = 0,  where



h1(«) and v(») are the ordinary demand functions and indirect utility function



associated with u(0.



     It is now necessary to assume that u(*) is strictly quasiconcave in both



x and q.



      Using subscripts to denote derivatives,  differentiate (9) and note that



q = g Cp> IT, u) = m (p, IT, u)  by Shephard's Lemma.  Equations similar to (9)



through (12) are presented by J. P. Neary and K. W. S.  Roberts (1980).


    11          A
      Note that TT(P, q, y) is not an inverse ordinary demand function in the



sense of Ronald W. Anderson (1980) because it involves  an income adjustment as



well as a price effect.



      It is commonly supposed that TT  > TT  when q  < q  --see, for example,



Figure 7.12 in Richard E. Just, Darrell  L.  Hueth, and Andrew Schmitz (1982)--but



this is not correct.  It can be shown that TT ^ TT  according as n ^ (I/a).



Since Za^rh + an = 1 by the Engel aggregation condition, where a^ = Pj*./(y +



Trq) and r^ = (y + irq) hVx^ TT° < ir1  if and only if Xa^^  n^^ _< °-



    •"•^This is actually the order of magnitude by which WTA measures exceed



WTP measures in the empirical  studies summarized in Table  3.2 of Ronald G.



Cummings, David S. Brookshire, and William D.  Schulze (forthcoming).

-------
                                     -17-






                                 REFERENCES





Anderson, Ronald W.,  "Some Theory of  Inverse Demand  for Applied Demand



    Analysis," European Economic  Review, 1980, 14, 281-90.



Bishop, Richard C. and Hebertein, Thomas A., "Measuring Values of



    Extra-Market Goods:  Are  Indirect Measures Biased," American Journal of



    Agricultural Economics, December  1979,  61, 926-30.



Coursey, Don L., Schulze, William D.  and Hovis, John J., "On the Supposed



    Disparity Between Willingness to  Accept and Willingness to Pay Measures of



    Value:  A Comment," mimeo., University  of Wyoming, Department of



    Economics, Laramie, Wyoming,  January 1984.



Cummings, Ronald G.,  Brookshire,  David S. and Schulze, William D., Valuing



    Public Goods:  An Assessment  of the Contingent Valuation Method, Totowa,



    N. J.:  Rowman and Allanheld, forthcoming.



Diewert, W. E., "A Note on Aggregation and  Elasticities of Substitution,"



    Canadian Journal  of Economics,  February 1974, 7, 12-20.



Freeman, A. Myrick, The Benefits  of Environmental Improvement:  Theory and



    Practice, Baltimore:  Johns Hopkins University Press, 1979.



Gordon, Irene M. and  Knetsch, Jack  L., "Consumer's Surplus Measures and the



    Evaluation of Resources," Land  Economics, February 1979, 55,  1-10.



Gorman, W. M., "Tricks With Utility Functions," in M. Artis and R. Nobay,



    eds., Essays in Economic  Analysis, New  York:  Cambridge University Press,



    1976.



Hanemann, W. Michael, "Quality and  Demand Analysis," in Gordon C. Rausser,



    ed., New Directions in Econometric Modeling and  Forecasting in U. S.



    Agriculture, Amsterdam:  North  Holland  Publishing  Co., 1982.

-------
                                     -18-
Just, Richard E.,  Hueth,  Darrell L. and Schmitz, Andrew, Applied Welfare



    Economics and Public  Policy, Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey:  Prentice-Hall,



    Inc., 1982.



Knetsch, Jack L. and Sinden,  J. A., "Willingness to Pay and Compensation



    Demanded:  Experimental Disparity  in Measures of Value," Quarterly Journal



    of Economics,  August  1984,  507-21.



Maler, Karl-Goran, Environmental Economics:  A Theoretical Inquiry, Balti-



    more:  Johns Hopkins  University Press, 1974.



Neary, J. P. and Roberts, K.  W. S., "The Theory of Household Behavior Under



    Rationing," European  Economic  Review, 1980, 13, 25-42.



Randall, Alan and Stoll,  John R.,  "Consumer's Surplus  in Commodity Space,"



    American Economic Review, June 1980, 71, 449-57.



Thayer, Mark A., "Contingent  Valuation Techniques for  Assessing Environmental



    Impacts:  Further Evidence," Journal of Environmental Economics and



    Management, 1981, 8,  27-44.



Willig, Robert, "Consumer's Surplus Without Apology,"  American Economic



    Review, September 1976, 66, 589-97.

-------
                                  CHAPTER 7



                       METHODS OF BENEFIT MEASUREMENT





    In the two preceding  chapters, we have spoken of benefits in a rather



general sense not specifying where they come from or how they might be meas-



ured in practice.  In Chapter  5,  for example, we assume the existence of a



benefit function for ecosystem recovery and examine how a decision on pollu-



tion control is affected  by the dynamics of recovery and the uncertainties



surrounding it.  In this  chapter  we look behind the benefit function.  What



kinds of benefits are provided by aquatic ecosystems, and how might they be



measured?  Here we take up the discussion begun in Chapter 1 drawing upon the



classification of benefits and measurement approaches suggested there.





I.  Aquatic Ecosystems as an Input to Production



    Aquatic ecosystems function as an  input to production whenever changes in



an ecosystem's characteristics affect the costs of providing a good or serv-



ice.  For example, the number  of  wetland acres available as a habitat for fish



may influence the cost of harvesting commercially valuable species.  The



quality of water withdrawn from rivers and lakes for municipal water supplies



and irrigation determines the  cost of subsequent water treatment and level of



agricultural productivity. Finally, just as air pollution may lead to the



chemical deterioration of materials, diminished water quality can lead to the



corrosion of household appliances and  industrial equipment.  Valuing the bene-



fits from improved environmental  quality when the environment acts as an input



to production is the focus of  this section.  We critically review a number



of earlier studies in the area and go on to suggest (and illustrate) some



improvements.

-------
    We focus on the examples  identified in Chapter 1:  supply of clean water



and harvest of commercial species.  Consider the former.  Wetlands reduce the



cost of water treatment by  removing or settling pollutants.  This can be



represented as a shift  in a marginal cost or supply curve along a given demand



curve.  An environmental improvement, such as provision of additional wet-



lands, would then involve a supply shift down and to the right, as from S to



S' in Figure 1, where the shaded area between old (S) and new (S1) supply



curves indicates the net welfare gain, the change in consumer and producer



surplus.



    This is probably a  typical case, but others are possible—and, it turns



out, relevant to some of the  existing literature.  One, in particular, is



worth noting.  Suppose  the  new cost or supply curve is simply the horizontal



axis.  In other words,  creation of the wetlands completely eliminates the need



for human inputs, at least  up to a point (represented by Q" on Figure 2).



Then the welfare gain,  illustrated in the figure, is the shaded area between



old and new supply curves up  to the point (Q1 on the figure) where demand



equals the old supply and between demand and new supply thereafter (up to



Q").  Note that this is less  than the area between the two supply curves.



Beyond Q', consumer willingness-to-pay for water is less than the old cost of



treatment so that the latter  is no longer relevant.



    This same point is  made more dramatically in Figure 3.  There the old cost



of treatment or supply curve  lies everywhere above the demand curve.  The



benefit of the environmental  improvement, represented as a shift in the supply



curve to coincide with the  horizontal axis, is then simply the area under the



demand curve (up to Q"). The area between the two supply curves, which is



just the area under the old curve, or the cost of providing treatment in the



absence of the wetlands, would overstate the benefit of having the wetlands



for this purpose.



                                    -2-

-------
p
            FIGURE 1
       WASTE ASSIMILATION
       BENEFIT PROVIDED BY
         THE ECOSYSTEM   .
              S=MC
                        S'=MC
                            Q
               -3-

-------
      FIGURE 2
WASTE ASSIMILATION
BENEFIT PROVIDED BY
  THE ECOSYSTEM
         -4-

-------
     FIGURE 3
WASTE ASSIMILATION
BENEFIT PROVIDED BY
  THE ECOSYSTEM
         -5-

-------
    This is essentially the difficulty with the pioneering and influential

study of the value of estuarine wetlands by Gosselink, Odum, and Pope (GOP,

1974).  They claim that an acre of estuarine wetland provides benefits which

would cost $2,500 per year if produced by man-made  treatment plants.  Shabman

and Batie (1977) are justifiably critical of this figure:


    "... the use of alternative estimates should  be governed by three
    considerations:   (1) the  alternative considered should provide the
    same services; (2) the alternative selected for the cost comparison
    should be the least-cost  alternative; and (3) there should be sub-
    stantial evidence that the service would be demanded by society if it
    were provided by the least-cost alternative.  GOP failed to subject
    their estimate to any of  these important tests."


    Park and Batie (1979) contend that GOP not only failed to test whether the

least-cost alternative would  be demanded, but that  their identification of

waste treatment plants as the least expensive alternative may be incorrect.

They argue that recent evidence suggests that adjustments in agricultural

practices (e.g., restriction  on the application of  fertilizers which "run off"

into estuarine waters) may be a less costly alternative to the construction of

treatment plants.  The criticism of the work of GOP is not to suggest that

waste assimilation is not an  important service provided by wetlands; however,

care must be taken when determining just how society values that service.

    Problems have also plagued efforts to value benefits which might be pro-

vided by aquatic ecosystems sometime in the future  but which are not currently

provided.  Instead of valuing the option to use a resource as an input to pro-

duction in the future in the  way suggested in Chapter 5, some studies have

calculated benefits as if the resource were already being used.  What is miss-

ing here is an estimation of  the likelihood that the resource will ever be
                                     -6-

-------
used and the timing of its use.  Gupta and Foster (GF, 1976) attempt to value



wetlands as a potential source  of water supply for the state of Massachusetts



and find that the state's wetlands could provide an annual benefit of $2,800



per acre.  Unfortunately, GF's  estimated benefit of wetlands1 preservation in



this regard is calculated as though the cost savings of using wetlands instead



of current sources were already realized.  Their finding, that wetlands would



provide a cheaper supply of water for Massachusetts, can be questioned in two



respects.  First, if wetlands are a cheaper alternative to current sources,



why are they not used?  Second,  if it is the existence of institutional bar-



riers which block their use, why won't those barriers continue to preclude the



tapping of wetlands as a supply of water in the future?  Although it is cer-



tainly true that the preservation of wetlands may be valuable because the



option to use them as a water source would be retained, this is not the bene-



fit GF estimate.  As a final point, their estimate of the total value of



undeveloped wetlands may be plagued by double counting problems.  If water



were taken from Massachusetts'  wetlands, would the same wetlands continue to



generate the recreational and amenity benefits they add to the water supply



benefits?



    We now turn to the commercial harvest example.  A substantial amount of



previous empirical \vork has sought to value the environment as input for this



purpose in ways not fully consistent with the deceptively simple approach dis-



cussed thus far and summarized  in Figure 1.  The estimated benefits variously



fail to analyze changes in  the  relevant cost structure, ignore price effects



of a change in production, and  rely on ad hoc measures like total or net reve-



nue.  As a measure of change in social welfare, revenue figures exhibit at
                                    -7-

-------
least two problems.  First,  they do not  reflect  the opportunity cost of pro-
ducing goods and services.   Second,  demand for many fish and shellfish species
is relatively price inelastic (Bell, 1970),  so an  increase  in production due
to an environmental improvement  results  in a decrease in total revenue, incor-
rectly implying that the improvement does not lead to a welfare gain.  About
the best that can be said for the revenue calculations (with or without price
effects) is that they are not relevant to the determination of a change in
combined consumer and producer surplus--our  preferred welfare measure.
    A Council on Environmental Quality (CEQ, 1970) study illustrates the same
difficulties in a somewhat different way.  The study reports that, due to the
practice of ocean dumping, one-fifth of  the  nation's shellfish beds are con-
taminated and closed. Assuming  the closed shellfish beds would be as produc-
tive as their open counterparts, the study concludes that an improvement in
water quality would result in a  25  percent increase in quantity produced and a
subsequent 25 percent increase in total  revenues.  The increase in total reve-
nues are claimed as the  gain to  society  of cleaning up the  shellfish beds.
However, as long as demand is not perfectly  elastic, an additional 25 percent
in the amount of shellfish supplied to the market  could only be sold if the
price of shellfish fell.  The estimate of CEQ of an additional $63 million in
shellfish revenues (the  additional  25 percent) is  clearly an overstatement.
But in any case the revenue  figures do not reflect costs or willingness to pay
for nonmarginal units and, hence, are not adequate measures of welfare.
    An important question to address, in valuing commercial fishing benefits,
is this:  What is the contribution  of the ecosystem to the  production proc-
ess?  It is a question some  studies have failed  to address.  Thus, GOP (1974),
                                    -8-

-------
in assessing the value of wetlands as a fish nursery, divide annual dockside



values of fish products landed by the total number of wetland acres to arrive



at a value per acre in production of fish.  Imputing all of the revenue from



commercial fishing to wetland acreage, however, ignores the contribution of



other fishing inputs like labor  and capital.



    The more recent study by Lynne, Conroy, and Prochaska (LCP, 1981) suggests



that it may be possible to isolate the contribution of environmental inputs to



production.  They develop a bioeconomic model in which human effort and marsh-



land are distinct inputs in the  production of blue crab off Florida's Gulf



Coast.  The population of blue crabs is assumed to be a function of the quan-



tity of local marshland acres.   Since the successful .harvesting of the crabs



is modeled to be dependent on their population level, marshlands, which act to



define the carrying capacity for blue crabs, appear as an input in the produc-



tion function.  The reduced form production function is estimated according to



the ordinary least-squares criterion; and, using the appropriate estimated



coefficients, a marginal product for an acre of wetlands is calculated.



Finally, the value of the marginal product for an acre is computed using cur-



rent dockside prices.  The study is laudable for valuing both marshland acre-



age and human input in the production of blue crabs.  However, the authors'



contention that the value of the marginal product is the relevant measure of



benefits provided by wetlands is incorrect.  Let us take up the analysis at



this point and develop an example in which notions of consumer and producer



surplus are correctly employed,  as in Figure 1, to evaluate the commercial



fishing benefits produced by the marshland.
                                     -9-

-------
     In keeping with the spirit of LCP, consider the optimization problem faced
by a price-taking firm or industry where price is P and the unit cost  of the
human effort input is, W:
 (1)    max P FCX.^ Y2) -  W
       X
The production process is posited to be a function, F(»), of two inputs:
one (X. ) which captures the efforts of man to harvest shellfish and another
.(X?) which  represents the contribution of an ecosystem variable like marsh-
land acreage.  The bar over X_ indicates that, for the time being, the acre-
age is  fixed.  Although we, like LCP, model human effort as a single input,
the number  of traps set, one many prefer to explicitly model the use of sev-
eral inputs so that substitution among them can be studied.
    We  assume that the production of blue crabs can be represented as a Cobb-
Douglas process.  Although the Cobb-Douglas form is no doubt a simplification
of  the  true production process (and is probably a poor approximation to
reality for extreme values of either input), we use it here because our main
purpose is  to demonstrate the procedure for calculating changes in combined
consumer and producer surplus.  Therefore, substituting for the production
function in equation (1) the Cobb-Douglas form and noting that cost minimiza-
tion is the dual problem to profit maximization, the optimization problem can
be  rewritten as
 (2)     min <£ = W X, + X(Q - A X? X)
                    i            l  L
                                     -10-

-------
where X is the Lagrange multiplier; Q  is output; and A, a, and b are parame-



ters.  Differentiating the Lagrangian  with  respect  to  the effort variable and



the Lagrange multiplier yields
(3)
        5^= W -  X A XT a Xf~  = 0
        dA,            £     1
(4)
           = Q - A X  X  = 0.
Since the production function is characterized by only one decision variable,



X,, equation (4) is the only one needed to solve for  the cost  function,




C(O.
(5)     Xj_ =
                xr
                    I/a
(6)     C(W, Q, XJ = W A"1/a X:b/a Q1/a.
Differentiating the cost function with respect to output  generates  the mar



ginal cost expression
        MC _ 9C _ W  -I/a rb/a n(l-a)/a
        ML - -   - -A     X2    Q
The blue crab industry also presumably faces a demand curve for  its  product.



A simple constant elasticity demand function is given in  (8), and  the corres-



ponding inverse demand function in (9):





                                     -11-

-------
(8)     Q = KP"m





(9)     P = K1/m Q"1/m





where K is a parameter and m is the (constant)  elasticity.  The profit-



maximizing firms will equate price  and marginal cost so that the equilibrium



level of blue crabs sold is given by






,  ,        Ta  1/m  I/a  K/O! ma/[m+(l-m)a]

(10)    Q =  - Ki/m Ai/a
            I W





The result in (10) holds for all relevant  values of marsh acreage, X~,



available for the biological promotion of  the blue  crab population.  There-



fore, we first calculate the equilibrium output associated with various levels



of wetland acreage, then we compute the  equilibrium price corresponding to the



output by use of equation (9).



    We proceed to calibrate the parameters of the model in order to construct



an example which is reasonably compatible  with  the  price, input, and output



data used by LCP.  We also incorporate their econometric finding that the mar-



ginal product of an acre of marsh is roughly 2-1/2  pounds of blue crab (annu-



ally).  Although the demand for shellfish  has been  found to be relatively



price-inelastic, as we noted earlier, we assume in  this case a high elasticity



since the Gulf Coast fishery is presumably not  the  sole source of blue crab in



the market.  Welfare gains associated with an increase in marshland habitat



(remember we are considering only gains  in the  blue crab industry for purposes



of this example) are calculated as  the change in consumer and producer sur-



plus.  These measures are presented in Table 1.  For example, for a demand



elasticity of -2.05, the net gain associated with an increase from 25,000
                                     -12-

-------
                         TABLE 1

Welfare Gain Associated with an Increase in Wetland Acreage
          (From an Initial Base of 25,000 Acres)
Elasticity
(m)
2.05
2.05
2.05
2.05
2.05
Wetland
acreage
OCj)
100.000
200,000
300,000
400,000
500,000
Number of
traps
(xL)
33.610
33,332
33,170
33,056
33,000
Change in
combined
surplus
191,389
294,290
356,843
402,316
435,829
                           -13-

-------
acres to 100,000 is $191,389.   Successive  increments  in acreage add less to
estimated benefits due to diminishing returns to the marshland input.
    The results of a sensitivity analysis,  in which different price elastici-
ties of demand [ranging from (-.25) to  (-3.45)] are used to calibrate the
model, indicate that, in this  particular model, the estimates of welfare gain
are reasonably robust to the choice of  an assumed price elasticity.
    The purpose of this exercise has been  to demonstrate that a theoretically
correct measure of welfare can be constructed and calculated on the basis of
empirical information about the impact  on  product supply (given demand) of a
change in ecosystem characteristics (here the number of wetland acres) which,
in turn, might be related to pollution  control.
    Of course, this has been a hypothetical exercise; and, in an actual case
study, one would econometrically estimate  the demand and production functions
necessary to conduct the welfare analysis.  Moreover, if the estimated demand
function includes an income variable, simple Marshallian consumer  surplus is
no longer the appropriate welfare measure.  Fortunately, for a variety of
functional forms for the demand function,  exact surplus measures are known and
available.
    A still more recent study, by Kahn  and Kemp (KK, 1985), appears to follow
the procedure we have outlined,  though  they use it to calculate a welfare
loss.  Specifically, they are  concerned with the effect the decline in sub-
merged aquatic vegetation (SAV)  is having on the various fisheries supported
by Chesapeake Bay.  SAV serves as an important link in  the estuarine food
chain, and KK attempt to quantify the welfare loss primarily to the striped
bass commercial fishery and, also, to other commercial  and sport fisheries
stemming from the reduction in SAV caused by agricultural runoff, discharges

                                    -14-

-------
from sewage treatment  plants and soil erosion, and the consequent reduction in



the carrying capacity  of the Bay.  Unlike LCP, KK are fortunate to have popu-



lation data on the striped bass.  With this, they can estimate a supply func-



tion which includes a  population variable for the fish and an equation which



relates SAV to fish.   After estimating a demand function for striped bass, KK



calculate the losses in consumer and producer surplus following incremental



reductions in SAV.  One criticism that can be made of their procedure is that,



since demand is estimated as a function of per capita income, a more exact



welfare measure than Marshallian consumer surplus could have been calculated.



Just for purposes of comparison with the welfare gains that we calculated for



the Florida Gulf Coast blue crab fishery, we observe that a 50 percent reduc-



tion in SAV is associated with an annual loss of approximately $4 million.



This is substantially  larger than the numbers in our example.  It is important



to note that KK are casting a  wider net, so to speak:  both commercial and



sport fishing, for several species, are considered.



    The studies just described are limited by their static nature.  Both exam-



ine the contribution of an environmental input to production assuming the



fishery is in bioeconomic equilibrium (i.e., the harvest rate of the marketed



species equals its growth rate).  To the extent that their data are comprised



of observations for years in which the fisheries were not in a steady state,



the regression coefficients they obtain will be biased as parameters of



steady-state models.   In addition, static approaches to fisheries economics



fail to evaluate the stream of benefits generated by fisheries as they move



from one equilibrium to the next.  As demonstrated in Chapter 3, the higher
                                    -15-

-------
trophic levels of damaged ecosystems may respond  slowly to pollution control


measures, and attempts to value control need to take this into account.


    The need for dynamic analysis  arises from  the recognition that  fishery


resources constitute capital  assets which yield a stream of benefits over


time, and it is in this framework  that we can  view proposed environmental


cleanup policies as potential investments.  Although much of the literature


now recognizes the dynamic nature  of fishery resources, with a few  articles


even explicitly recognizing the dynamic links  between predator and  prey


species (see Clark, 1976, and Ragozin and Brown,  1985), the literature has not


considered the management of  fisheries' environmental problems in a dynamic


context.


    A framework for finding an optimal management strategy when a fishery is


confronted with pollution and open-access problems might look something like


the following.  The management problem is one  of  simultaneously determining


harvesting and pollution control policies to maximize the present discounted


value of net benefits generated by the fishery.   In the most general notation,


i.e., making no assumptions about  the forms of economic or biologic functions,


the management problem is




                    00         t
(11)      Max       Z  (1 + r)~  NB[E(t), Z(t), X(t)]

        E(t),Z(t)  t=0



subject to




(12)    X(t+l) - X(t) = f{E(t), Q[Z(t)], X(t)}



and



(13)    X(0) = XQ





                                    -16-

-------
where r is a discount rate,  NB(»)  is a net benefit function (e.g., combined



consumer and producer surplus),  E  is fishing effort, Z is pollution control,



X is the stock of the, harvested  species, and Q is the level of environmental



quality.  Further realism may be given to the model by including additional



equations of motion [like equation (12)] which represent the growth rates of



other species in the ecosystem and establish links between distinct levels of



the food chain.  Modeling species  interaction may be of particular importance



if pollution directly affects growth rates at the lower trophic levels, as



demonstrated in Chapter  3.   However, the introduction of biological inter-



action among species also poses  the problem of selecting an appropriate model



from the available alternatives  (see May, 1973, for a description of the vari-



ous ways in which species interaction may be modeled).  Interactions can be



complex and models like  the  Lotka-Volterra used in Chapters 3 and 4 and also



in the studies reviewed  in this  section which imply simple feeding hierarchies



rather than complex food webs may  be misleading (see Harte, 1985).



    A key feature of the solution  of the optimization problem stated in equa-



tions (11) through (13)  may  be the interdependence of the two control vari-



ables, allowable fishing effort, and pollution control.  For example, if the



level of the fish stock  is below the optimum, the derived solution to the



management problem may include the enactment of stringent pollution controls



to enable the fish population to recover.  The solution may also include con-



current restrictions on  fishing  effort (possibly even prohibition) so that the



eventual benefits of costly  pollution control may be realized.



    The fisheries management problem is further complicated by the fact that



decisions must be made in the face of uncertainty.  As discussed in Chapter 4,
                                     -17-

-------
uncertainty pervades the modeling of species interaction; and this is com-



pounded by uncertainty about  ecosystem responsiveness to pollution control.



When uncertainty about .the  values of economic variables is introduced, the



optimization problem becomes  a  very difficult stochastic control problem in-



deed.  If it is the case that uncertainty about the parameters of the model



can be reduced by research  or the acquisition of  information through experi-



ence, management strategies should ideally be evaluated with the aid of



closed-loop models in which policy decisions are  subject to revison as new



information becomes available,  as discussed in Chapter 5 (see also Rausser,



1978).






 II.   Aquatic Ecosystems as a Final  Good



      When  an aquatic  ecosystem is conceived of as ;a final good the benefits



 of enhancing the ecosystem typically take the form of improved  opportunities



 for water-related recreation.   These benefits can be estimated using the



 methodologies discussed in Chapter  6—either contingent valuation/behavior



 experiments or the revealed  preference  approach based on fitting demand



 functions for visiting  alternative recreation sites (also called the "travel-cost"



 approach).   Some of the methodological  issues involved in contingent valuation



 experiments are discussed in Cummings, Brookshire and Schulze (1986),



 Hanemann (1985), and Carson  and Mitchell (forthcoming).   Issues involved



 in  the travel-cost approach are discussed in  Bockstael,  Hanemann and  Strand



 (1984) and Smith and  Desvousges (1986).



      The main challenge confronting practitioners of travel-cost  studies is



 the need to handle the allocation of water-based  recreation activities  among



 multiple  sites  differing in their  environmental  quality attributes in a manner



 consistent with the utility  maximization hypothesis.  Two particular aspects



                                     -18-

-------
stand out — the selection of appropriate functional forms for  the  ordinary
demand functions, and the need to deal with corner  solutions.   Taking  the
question of functional forms first,  the problem is to  select a set of functions
for the ordinary demands,  x. = h  (p.q.y), i = 1,..,N, defined at the be-
ginning of Chapter 6.  In this  context x. is the number of  visits to re-
creation  site i by a household over some period of time (e.g.,  the fishing
season), p = (p,,.-,pN)  where p.  is  some measure of the cost of visiting
the i    site,  q = (q1,..,qN)  where q is some vector of attributes of the
i    site (including water  quality,  etc.) and y is either  the  household's
total income or its total expenditure on recreation activities.  The problem
is  that, if these demand  functions  are to  be consistent  with some utility
maximization hypothesis,  they must satisfy certain economic integrability
conditions, including (i)  the  adding up condition and (ii) the symmetry and
(iii) negative semidefiniteness of the  matrix of Slutsky terms, S  =iS,, 3  , where
     These  requirements  are by no  means  trivial and  impose significant
restrictions on the eligible  functional forms.  For example a  demand system
of the form
                ***.•--   *;-£;?;, * JfjJ       ia',-->M                  (15a)
where          *t* «• + $ *>^*                                      (15b)
                   •    +        .                                       (15c)
                              .
which is employed in Smith and Desvousges (1986),  would appear to violate
the symmetry of the s.,  terms.  Other generalizations of the semi-log form
to systems of multiple demand equations are examined by Hanemann and Lafrance
(1983),  where it is shown that the  symmetry conditions place very stringent
                                 -19-

-------
(and empirically implausible)  restrictions on  the  underlying direct  utility



function.   This does not mean that there are no suitable  functional forms:



systems such  as the Linear Expenditure System — Binkley  and Hanemann  (1975)



and other members of the Generalized Gorman Polar Form family  of indirect



utility  functions
can certainly be  employed.



     The  second  issue — the  phenomenon of  corner solutions — is more trouble-



some.  This refers to a situation where some of the x.'s are zero — a household



visits some of the available  sites,  but not all of them.  The  conventional theory



of consumer behavior is developed under the assumption of an interior solution



to the utility maximization problem   (1)  in Chapter 6 — i.e., a  solution  where



all the x.'s are positive.   Modifying  this  theory to  deal with non-consumption



of certain goods  (non- visitation of certain sites) — a phenomenon that is



overwhelmingly apparent  in  micro-data  sets — is a rather complex task.   The



problems involved, and some possible solutions, are examined  in Chapters



8-10 of Bockstael,  Hanemann and Strand.



     A common approach  to  modelling corner solutions is to decompose  consumer



choices into two  elements:   the  selection of a total  level of recreation activity,



x =Zx-.  and then the  allocation of this total among the alternative  possible



sites  based  on some  type  of shares model



                                    ^        0=1,.., A)                  (17)
where ft., the share of total visits assigned to the i   site, satisfies
                              ...                                      (18)



Statistical models  such as logit and probit can be used to  estimate the share




equations,  and these models can be related to a utility maximization  hypothesis.




But, at the present time, it is often difficult to obtain a utility-theoretic




                                  -20-

-------
justification for the "macro  visitation equation"  determining x, and to



integrate  it with the share  equations in a theoretically consistent manner.



That is to say, one would like the determination of "x and   iTl ,  .. , 'T^j   to



originate  in a  single,  simultaneous utility maximization procedure.  Some



models which  permit this  have recently  been developed,  but they are relatively



difficult to  estimate.  The resolution of these issues represents one of the



frontiers  of research  for  the  travel cost approach.
                                  -21-

-------
                                BIBLIOGRAPHY






Bell, F. W.   The Future of the World's Fishery Resources:  Forecasts of De-



    mand, Supply and Prices  to the Year 2000 with a Discussion of Implications



    for Public Policy, U. S. National Marine Fisheries Service, No. 65-1, 1970.



Clark, C. W.   Mathematical Bioeconomics.  New York:  John Wiley and Sons, Inc.,



    1976.



Council on Environmental Quality.  Ocean Dumping:  A National Policy. Washing-



    ton, D.  C.:   Government  Printing Office, 1970.



Gosselink, J. G., Odum, E. P., and Pope, R. M.  The Value of the Tidal Marsh,



    Center for Wetland Resources, Louisiana State University, No. LSU-SG-74-03,



    1974.



Gupta, T. R., and Foster, J. H.  "Economics of Freshwater Wetland Preservation



    in Massachusetts," in J. S. Larson, ed., Models for Assessment of Fresh-



    water Wetlands,  Water Resources Center, University of Massachusetts,



    No. 32,  1976.



Harte, J.  Consider  a Spherical Cow.  Los Altos:  William Kaufmann, Inc., 1985.



Kahn, J. R.,  and Kemp, W. M.  "Economic Losses Associated with the Degradation



    of an Ecosystem: The Case of Submerged Aquatic Vegetation in Chesapeake



    Bay," Journal of Environmental Economics and Management, Vol. 12 (1985),



    pp. 246-63.



Lynne, G. D., Conroy, P., and Prochaska, F. J.  "Economic Valuation of Marsh



    Areas for Marine Production Processes," Journal of Environmental Economics



    and Management,  Vol. 8  (1981), pp. 175-86.




May, R. M.  Stability and Complexity in Model Ecosystems.  Princeton, New



    Jersey:   Princeton University Press, 1973.
                                    -22-

-------
Park, W.  M., and Batie, S. S.   "Methodological Issues Associated with



    Estimation of Economic Value of Coastal Wetlands in Improving Water



    Quality,"  Virginia Polytechnic Institute and State University,



    No. VPI-SG-79-09, 1979.



Ragozin,  D.  L., and Brown, G., Jr.  "Harvest Policies and Nonmarket Valuation



    in a  Predator-Prey System," Journal of Environmental Economics and



    Management, Vol. 12 (1985), pp. 155-68.



Rausser,  G.  C. "Active Learning, Control Theory, and Agricultural Policy,"



    American Journal of Agricultural Economics, Vol. 60 (1978), pp. 476-90.



Shabman,  L.  A., and Batie, S.  S.  "Estimating the Economic Value of Natural



    Coastal  Wetlands:  A Cautionary Note," Coastal Zone Management, Vol.  4




    (1977),  pp. 231-47.



 Binkley, Clark S.  and Hanemann, W. Michael,  (1975)  The Recreation Benefits



     of Water  Quality Improvement.   Cambridge, Mass. :Urban Systems



     Research & Engineering,  Inc.



 Bockstael,  Nancy E., Hanemann, W. Michael and Strand, Jr., Ivar E., (1984)



     Measuring the Benefits of Water Quality Improvements Using  Recreation



     Demand Models.   University of Maryland,  Department of Agricultural



     and Resource Economics,  College Park,  MD.



 Carson, Richard T.  and Mitchell, Robert C.,  Using Surveys To Value



     Public  Goods:   The Contingent Valuation Method,  Washington, D.C.:



     Resources for  the Future,  Inc.  (forthcoming).



 Cummings,  R.G., Brookshire,  D.S. and Schulze,  W.D.,  (1986) Valuing



     Environmental  Goods:  An  Assessment of the Contingent Valuation Method



     Tolowa, NJ: Rowman and  Allanheld.



 Hanemann,  W. Michael (1985),  "Some Issues in Discrete -  and Continuous -



     Response Contingent Valuation Studies," Northeastern Journal of Agri-



     cultural Economics ,  April 1985.



                                     -23-

-------
               and Lafrance, Jeffery T., (1983)  "On the Integration
    of  Some Common Demand Systems," Staff Paper No.  83-10,  Dept.  of



   Agricultural Economics  and Economics,  Montana State  University, Bozeman.



Smith, V. Kerry and  Desvousges,  William L. (1986), Measuring Water Quality



    Benefits, Boston: Kluwer-Nijhoff Publishing Co.)
                                 -24-

-------
                              Chapter 8.




                             Further Work








     Our  present  intention is to  proceed  in two areas:   (1) comparative




analysis of models for policy evaluation; and (2)  development of a case




study.




     The  first task,  the comparative  analysis, is  intended  to  further




integrate the  ecologic and economic models  developed  in  earlier chapters,




and to compare the results obtained with those of variant versions of the




models.  Both aspects of this task are  important.  The  first  involves a




tighter linking (than any in the  present  report) of a model of ecosystem




recovery  with  a model of dynamic  optimization under uncertainty.  The idea




is to develop the capability to evaluate control policies  leading to




ecosystem recovery,  taking  account  of  the (probabilistic) state of the




system  over  time and at  any point  in time.




     The  second aspect of this  task, comparative  analysis of different




models,  is  dictated by our lack of knowledge about population dynamics in a




recovering  aquatic ecosystem.  In chapters 3 and  4  these  dynamics were




described by perhaps the simplest model  for  the purpose, the Lotka-Volterra.




This was  sufficient to obtain  interesting  results about qualitative  features




of recovery dynamics and the propagation  of uncertainty.   But as we move




toward application (as in the  case study described below)  it  becomes




important to determine whether  the results are robust,  i.e., whether they




continue  to  hold for equally  plausible, though more  complex,  specifications




of ecosystem population dynamics.   Further,  we need to explore the notion of




robustness  itself.   Two  models may  yield seemingly  quite different




predictions about the  nature and timing of recovery, yet imply the same






                                    1

-------
ranking of policy alternatives.  For example, one model may predict recovery




of a  fish population  to  50%  of its  pre-pol lution level  (ignoring




uncertainty) within five years of  the  imposition of some control measure,




whereas another may predict recovery to  just 10%.  But  the net present value




of control may be positive  in  both  cases.   In any  event, considerable




further work is needed,  in our judgment, on model development,  integration,




and comparative analysis, before  we are ready  to tackle  a case study.




     Turning now to the case study, we wish to pose  a  basic  question:  What




do we want to  get  out of a case study?  Two things, it seems to us.  First,




of course, we want quantitative results.  What  are the benefits  of a




particular control option?   Second,  however,  we want to know what the




results depend on.  Partly,  this is traditional sensitivity analysis.   How




are results affected  by changes in assumptions about the discount rate,




about a  parameter describing interaction between the first and  second




trophic  levels,  and   so on.  But more importantly,  we   want  to  try to




establish links between results and the types of models used to generate




them.  This task  clearly links back to our proposed work in the first area,




comparative analysis of models for policy evaluation.  The difference is




that now we are proposing to  go  through  the exercise  in a real case, with




real  numbers.



     With these objectives in mind, we wish to  propose a "double-barreled"




study.  First,  we would look at a relatively simple lake ecosystem, and one




for  which there also  exists fairly  good data on pollution  control and




subsequent recovery.   A leading candidate here is Lake Washington, in the




state of Washington.   The  idea would  be to "field-test" our  modeling




approach in a  relatively favorable  setting.




     Second,  we  would  like  to  tackle San Francisco Bay.   The  Bay is of

-------
course a much  larger and more complex aquatic ecosystem, a marine estuary




with substantial  wetlands.   Further, existing data are less reliable  than




for Lake Washington.  Yet even with these difficulties, we  feel  the Bay is




an appropriate subject for study by this project,  for several  reasons.




First,  it  is  economically  important,  a major influence  on  the natural




resource base  (including climate) of a metropolitan area of more  than  five




million people.   Second, the Bay is the subject of  considerable current




research and policy interest, at both the state and national  levels.  Third,




a  related point,  the Bay  ecosystem includes the major remaining wetlands in




Northern California, and wetlands are themselves the subject of much current




interest.  Fourth, a study of San Francisco Bay would nicely complement




existing work on  the major  east  coast  marine estuarine  system,  the




Chesapeake Bay.  Fifth,  clearly travel costs would be  minimized by choice of




the  Bay.  Sixth,  and  finally,  despite,  or  perhaps  because  of,  the




difficulties,  we  regard the proposed study as an exciting challenge.




     We should note  that, again because of the magnitude of the task and the




potential difficulties, we do not propose to complete a study of the Bay




within 12 to  18  months following  submission of the final report on the




current study.  But we certainly would anticipate completion of parts of the




task,  which might  stand on their own as interesting and useful  research




results.

-------